- Amy Olberding, 2019, The Wrongness of Rudeness, Oxford University Press
This blog is concerned with most topics in applied philosophy. In particular it is concerned with autonomy, love and other emotions. comments are most welcome
Thursday, 28 November 2019
Civil Discourse
Wednesday, 23 October 2019
The Doctrine of Informed Consent and Respect for Autonomy
In this posting I want to examine the relationship, if any,
between the doctrine of informed consent and respect for autonomy. In doing so
I will try to answer three important questions. Firstly is the doctrine of
informed consent based on respecting autonomy or is it a sui generis doctrine? The
fact we talk about a doctrine of informed consent seems to suggest the latter. Secondly
if informed consent isn’t based on respecting autonomy should it be so based?
Lastly if informed consent is based on respecting autonomy what type autonomy
should that be?
Is informed consent based on respecting patient autonomy? According
to Charles Foster the doctrine of informed consent is in a mess.
“Informed consent, in practice, is a bad joke. It’s a
notion created by lawyers, and like many such notions it bears little
relationship to the concerns that real humans have when they’re left to
themselves, but it creates many artificial, lucrative, and expensive concerns.”
Practical
Ethics
Let us accept that the principles underlying informed
consent are unclear. Let us try to start understanding these underlying
principles by examining the process of informed consent in practice. When
taking informed consent a patient’s doctors propose some form of treatment and
provide the patient with the information he needs in order to make a good decision.
The patient then agrees or refuses to agree to this treatment. What is the
purpose of this process? The purpose of the agreement part of this process
seems clear. The agreement part prevents the patient being treated against his
will and his doctors from being accused of assault. The purpose of the
information part is different. The purpose of this part is to enable patients
to make good decisions. What exactly do we mean by a good decision? A decision
which is in the patient’s best interests or an autonomous decision? In a
medical setting a decision which is in a patient’s best interests is one which minimises
harm to the patient, maintains or
improves his physiological health. The amputation of a patient’s gangrenous leg
would be an example of acting in a patient’s best interests by minimising harm.
The provision of drugs to control a patient’s blood pressure would be an
example of acting in a patient’s best interests by maintaining his physical
health. A kidney transplant would be an example of improving a patient’s
health. Autonomy is concerned with self-government and very roughly speaking an
autonomous decision is one by which someone governs himself. However
self-government is simply governing oneself and need not always be good
government. We can govern ourselves badly. Let us assume that a patient simply
wants to accept his doctors’ judgement about his treatment and doesn’t want to
receive any additional information. Intuitively such a decision can be seen as
a decision by which he governs himself and as a result is an autonomous
decision for after all we can simply choose to follow our lawyer’s advice and
most would regard such a decision as autonomous. However under The General
Medical Council’s proposed guidelines such a decision might not be seen as a
valid informed consent decision.
“If, after discussion, a patient
insists that they don’t want even this basic information, you must explain the
potential consequences of them not having it. This might include being unable
to proceed if you are not confident that their consent would be valid, or if
you are not confident that the proposed course of action would be beneficial to
the patient overall.” (1)
In the light of the above it
would appear that The General Medical Council’s guidelines are not really based
on respecting autonomy and the purpose of providing information when taking
informed consent is to enable patients make decisions which are in their best
interests.
It might be objected that I have
only briefly sketched a certain account of autonomy and that a different
account might mean that the doctrine of informed consent could be based on respect
for autonomy. After all in my brief account the patient in my example above who
fully trusted his doctors to make a decision on his behalf might wake up to unexpectedly
find himself with only one leg. It might be suggested such a decision isn’t an
autonomous one and that we should adopt a more substantive account. For the
sake of argument let us assume an autonomous decision must be one that concurs
with some generally accepted set of norms. If these norms are to be generally
accepted then they must concern what is good for people. Autonomous decisions become
linked to good decisions. An autonomous decision must be a good
decision and a bad decision cannot be an autonomous one. I now want to argue against
accepting such a substantive account of autonomy. If an autonomous decision
must be a good decision because it must concur with some accepted norms then it
might be questioned whether such an account of autonomy is really doing any useful
work. A substantive account of autonomy puts itself out of business because we
only need to consider good and bad decisions. We don’t need to consider
autonomous decisions at all. Using a substantive account of autonomy an
autonomous decision must of necessity be a good decision according to some
accepted norms whilst on a content neutral account of autonomy an autonomous
decision can be a bad decision. Of course it is preferable that an autonomous
decision, using a content neutral account of autonomy, is a good decision which
benefits the decision maker but the purpose of respecting autonomy remains
simply to respect the decision maker as a person and the actual decision
doesn’t of necessity need to be a good one. If we accept the above then we have
two options. Firstly we could abandon the pretence that underlying the doctrine
of informed consent is respect for autonomy or secondly we could accept that underlying
the doctrine of informed consent is respect for a content neutral or primitive
account of autonomy and modify the doctrine accordingly.
If we accept the above then there is not only a difference
in complexity between substantive and primitive accounts of autonomy but more
importantly these different accounts have a different focus. A substantive
account focusses on respecting good decisions, a primitive account focusses
respecting persons by simply accepting their decisions. Adopting a primitive
account requires adopting a certain degree of humility. Let us accept that if
the concept of autonomy is to remain a relevant one that it must be a primitive
or content neutral concept based on respecting persons. Such a concept might be
classed as a Millian concept. In the rest of this posting ‘autonomy’ will refer
to such a concept. Let us also accept the first of the above options that the
doctrine of informed consent is a doctrine in its own right and isn’t based on
respect for autonomy. The informed consent process starts with a patient’s
doctors proposing a course of treatment which they believe to be in his best
interests, the patient then consents or refuses to consent to the proposed
treatment. I argued above that the purpose of informed consent is to get a patient
to consent to treatment which his doctors believe to be in his best interests.
In almost all cases the patient simply consents and no problems arise. What is
interesting are cases in which the patient refuses to consent. In these cases according
to the doctrine of informed consent a patient’s doctors must be sure, or take
steps to ensure, that the patient knows the consequences of his actions. However
let us assume that the patient maintains his refusal of consent. By what
standards is his competence to refuse treatment measured by and how is it assessed?
If someone takes a driving test his competence to drive is based on his actual
driving. This is not true when assessing someone’s ability to give informed
consent. Someone’s competence to give informed consent isn’t based on his
actual decisions. His decision might of course trigger a competence assessment
but his competence isn’t dependent on his actual decision. Someone’s
competence to give informed consent is based on his ability to make good
decisions based on his best interests. I would suggest that someone who has the
ability to make good decisions based on his best interests is self-governing,
is autonomous.
As mentioned above the purpose of a driving test is to
measure someone’s competence to drive and the criteria by which his competence
is measured is by his actual driving. The same isn’t true of informed consent.
I have argued above that the purpose of informed consent is to enable patients
to make good decisions. I have further argued above that the way in which a
patient’s competence to make good decisions is assessed is by his ability to
make autonomous decisions. Such a mismatch creates problems and perhaps is one
of the reasons why the doctrine of informed consent is in a mess. Two solutions
might be suggested to remedy this mismatch. First the purpose of informed
consent should be to enable a patient to make a good decision in particular
circumstances and the patient’s competence should be assessed by his ability to
make a good decision in these circumstances. Secondly the purpose of informed
consent is to enable a patient to make an autonomous decisions and his competence
to do so should be assessed by his ability to make an autonomous decision.
Let us consider the first of these options. Let us accept
that a good decision is one that is in the decision maker’s best interests and
that a decision is a competent one only if the decision is in the decision
maker’s best interests. Clearly if someone makes a decision to do something
which he believes isn’t in his best interests then he isn’t making a good
decision. If a patient’s competence depends on him making a good decision then
he is incompetent. Perhaps he is paralysed by fear. However in practice most
people make decisions which they believe to be in their best interests.
Moreover in a medical setting there is usually agreement between the patient
and his doctors about what these best interests are. Unfortunately in a few
cases in which there might be disagreement about what is in a patient’s best
interests. Let us accept that a patient who makes a decision which he believes
to be in his best interests, but which is generally believed not to be in his
medical interests by his doctors, is making an incompetent decision. In
practice if a child or cognitively challenged adult makes a decision which
others believe isn’t in his best interests his competence might be questioned
and he might be treated against his will. Unfortunately if a competent decision
must be a good decision then the same considerations would seem to apply to all
patients. Accepting the above would mean that if any patient makes a decision
which is generally regarded as not being his best interests then his decision
is an incompetent one. In these circumstances the patient’s doctors might be
accused of paternalism or even epistemic arrogance. Fortunately in most cases a
patient’s medical best interests and what the patient believes are his overall
best interests concur. However this isn’t true in all cases. In cases in which
these interests don’t concur do we insist that a competent decision is based on
a patient’s best medical interests or what he believes to be in his overall
best interests? Practical considerations and the need to avoid the charge of
paternalism suggest that we should choose the second option. However if we
accept that a patient is making a competent decision when it concurs with what
he believes are in his overall best interests we are back to assessing a
patient’s competence to make a good decision by assessing his ability to make
an autonomous one and the above mismatch remains unresolved.
The above difficulties suggest
that we should choose the second option. The purpose of informed consent should
be to enable patients to make autonomous decisions about their treatment and that
any competence assessment should be based on their ability to make autonomous
decisions. This provides an answer to the second of my three initial questions.
Informed consent should be based on respect for patient autonomy. Moreover if a
substantive account of autonomy makes itself redundant as I have argued above
the type of autonomy underlying informed consent must be a primitive or
Milliian account. This answers the third of my three initial questions. Accepting
this option has consequences for the amount of information which needs to be
supplied to patients when taking informed consent. In the past under the
doctrine of informed consent a patient’s doctors determined what risks the
patient should be made aware of. However the Montgomery ruling Montgomery
ruling stated that a patient’s doctors must ensure that the patient
is aware of any and all the risks involved. If patients are to make informed
consent decisions based on respect for autonomy they don’t always need to be
aware of any and all the risks and the Montgomery ruling seems to suggest that
informed consent shouldn’t be based on respect for a primitive account of
autonomy. However if we accept that if an account of autonomy is to remain a
meaningful account that it must be a primitive account then if informed consent
is based on respect for autonomy it must
be based on a primitive account. Accepting the above means that a patient’s
doctors should have a dialogue with him about any suggested medical procedure.
How this dialogue proceeds shouldn’t be preordained by some doctrine but driven
by the patient’s needs. In most cases this will include informing him about any
major risks and life changes he faces. However some patients might need less or
more information in order to make an autonomous decision. As mentioned above an
autonomous agent can make an autonomous decision to trust the advice of his lawyer or financial advisor.
If someone is non-autonomous someone else might be given power of attorney to
act on his behalf. Are doctors any less trustworthy than lawyers or financial
advisors? It would seem to me they aren’t. Does then the context in which
informed consent takes place differ from other contexts such as the law and
finance in respect of an agent’s ability to make autonomous decisions? Provided
the patient isn’t incapacitated by fear it isn’t. It follows if informed
consent is based on respect for autonomy that a patient should be able to make
a competent decision simply to take his doctors’ advice. Other patients might
need more information than is usually supplied in order to make an autonomous
consent decision. Doctors should make it clear that they are willing to supply
more information when this is requested. For instance it might matter greatly
to a Jehovah’s witness whether there would be any possibility of a blood transfusion
however remote this possibility might be.
It might be objected that I
have already introduced an example which shows that it would be absurd to base
the doctrine of informed consent on a non-substantive or Millian account of
autonomy. Let us agree that if we accept such an account that a patient can
make a competent decision simply to trust his doctor. Let us recall the patient
with the gangrenous leg. Let us assume that this patient simply wants to trust
his doctor and refuses to listen to any information provided. He wakes up and
unexpectedly finds he has only one leg. Such a scenario seems absurd. Perhaps
then the basis of informed consent should be a substantive account or the
doctrine of informed consent should be a self-contained doctrine. Let us assume
the patient still wants to simply trust his doctors and refuses to listen to
any information concerning his procedure. Should he should be forced to listen
to brief details connected to his proposed treatment? Do doctors really want to
force someone to listen? Is it possible to force someone to listen and digest
information? Should he be left to die? In this situation it seems more likely
that the patient would be judged as incompetent. He would then be treated in
accordance with his best interests and his leg removed. He wakes up with only
one leg. In this case adopting a substantive account of autonomy or considering
the doctrine of informed consent as a sui generis doctrine changes nothing. It
follows that whilst adopting a non-substantive might lead to some highly
undesirable consequences in a few rare cases that it doesn’t lead absurd ones.
- Supporting patient choices about health and
care: Draft Guidance for consultation, GMC, 2019, [33]-[35]
Thursday, 26 September 2019
Lying and Autonomy
We live in a world surrounded by fake news and lies. According to Terry Pratchett in the Truth “A lie can run round the world before the truth has got its boots on.” However even if lies sometimes spread more easily than the truth, perhaps in part because they are more palatable and we want to believe them, in the long term the truth matters because the truth has persistence which lies don’t. Perhaps the dwindling number of climate change deniers supports the above. Are there any circumstances in which lying is beneficial? Stephen Rainey writing in practicalethics suggests that some lies “can also be a kindness, when the truth might serve no good”. Let us accept that in most circumstances lying damages both individuals by depriving them of the truth and trust. Nonetheless is Rainey correct when he suggests some lies might be beneficial in some circumstance? For instance might a government be acting beneficently if it lied about the harm done by the coronavirus to prevent panic? The fact that lying hasn’t been eliminated from human culture over time suggests it isn’t harmful in all circumstances. In this posting I want to examine what these circumstances might be. It might be thought that this is merely an interesting rather than important question, however in seeking to answer this question raises a further question about the balance between acting beneficently and respecting autonomy. I will argue that if I lie to someone and even if my lie benefits him that I also fail to respect him by failing to respect his autonomy.
Most people have no problems with defining a lie. The definition I
shall adopt here is that of Sam Harris
“To lie is to intentionally mislead others when they expect honest
communication.” lying
Lies so defined can explicit when liars intentionally give someone false information. Lies can also be acts of omission when the liar intentionally withholds information others expect him to provide. Perhaps passive aggression can be a form of lying if it involves withholding information. Liars can be practised by individuals, institutions or even governments.
Let us now consider whether it is ever acceptable to lie for beneficent reasons. Because lying is so prevalent our intuitions suggest that it is. Everyday examples seem to confirm our intuitions. For instance the mother who lies to her child by saying she has no money left when her child demands a second ice cream. Someone who lies to his partner about a surprise party. A government which lies to its citizens about the seriousness of some disease outbreak, such as that caused by the coronavirus, in order to prevent mass panic. Nonetheless as Harris points out we need to be extremely cautious about our intuitions. Firstly we must be sure about our motives being really beneficent. Is the mother above really worried about her child becoming obese or simply taking an easy option? Secondly we must be careful not to damage trust. The government above might avert mass panic but in the future its pronouncements on health matters might not be so readily trusted. If a lie cannot be maintained then it is better not to lie at all in order to retain trust. The Chinese government’s attempt to suppress the full extent of the coronavirus outbreak in Wuhan seems to support the above. However let us accept that there are at least some cases in which we might lie for beneficent reasons in which our motives are clear and we don’t damage trust. For instance it would be perfectly acceptable to lie to a stalker carrying a knife about the whereabouts of his ex-girlfriend.
Let us accept that in certain circumstances we can act beneficently by lying, telling white lies. Let us further accept that in some of these circumstances trust isn’t damaged. In such circumstances is Rainey correct when he suggests that lying might be an act of kindness? It certainly seems that because we are behaving beneficently that our actions might be classed as acts of kindness. However I now want to argue even if our lies serve a beneficent purpose and can be classed as acts of kindness that nonetheless it is almost always wrong to lie. Most pet owners are kind to their pets and act beneficently towards them but most people don’t want to be treated in the same way as pets however kindly. They want to be recognised as the sort of creatures who can make their own decisions. To be autonomous. Autonomous people govern themselves and this requires making decisions that matter to them. To make decisions that matters to someone requires information and lying deprives him of some of that information. It follows if we lie to someone we fail to respect his autonomy. Moreover if someone becomes aware of being lied to this lack of respect is a form of rudeness see the philosophy of rudeness.html or form of contempt. It further follows if we believe it is right to respect someone’s autonomy that we shouldn’t lie. It further follows if a government lies to or intentionally misleads the electorate over some issue such as Brexit that it not only deprives the electorate of some of the information needed to make a good decision it also shows a lack of respect for the electorate and perhaps even democracy itself. This lack of respect is similar to the lack of respect many colonialists showed for native people even if their motives were beneficent.
I now want to consider two objections to accepting the above conclusion. My first argument will be based on respecting autonomous persons and my second on respecting autonomous decisions. Firstly it might be objected that we should give precedence to acting beneficently over respecting autonomy and that sometimes lying is the only effective way to act in someone’s best interests. I now want to present two counter arguments against accepting the above. Let us accept that if we need to lie to someone in order to act in what we believe to be their best interests that there must be a clash between what we believe to be in their best interests and what they perceive to be in their best interests. It would appear that we believe we know better than the agent about what is in his best interests or should be in his best interests. In this situation we might be accused of epistemic arrogance. Secondly I would argue if we accept the above objection we don’t really understand what respect means. We can sometimes act beneficently towards someone but part time respect isn’t respect we can’t respect someone only some of the time. We can of course respect someone’s courage but not her wit. However when we respect her as a person we can’t respect her only some of the time. Part time respect just isn’t respect at all. It follows if we lie to someone in order to act beneficently we are not giving precedence to acting beneficently over respecting autonomy we are in reality failing to respect autonomy at all.
Now let us consider respecting autonomous decisions. Let accept to respect an autonomous decision means to accept it. It might be objected that any difference between respecting someone’s autonomous decisions and acting beneficently towards him is largely illusory. This objection depends on accepting a substantive account of autonomy in which autonomous decisions must concur with some accepted norms, autonomous decisions must be good decisions. Accepting such an account means that if we lie to someone, who is making a bad decision, in order to act beneficently towards him we are still respecting his autonomy. Bad decisions just aren’t autonomous decisions. However I am reluctant to accept a substantive account of autonomy. A substantive account has become more prominent recently largely in order to make respecting autonomy concur better with the doctrine of informed consent. Unfortunately as I have argued elsewhere a substantive account of autonomy puts itself out of business, see autonomy and toleration . If autonomous decisions must be good decisions in accord with some accepted norms then we can just consider good decisions and autonomy becomes a redundant concept. Of course if someone is to make an autonomous decision he mustn’t be misled or coerced but it follows that if autonomy is to remain a meaningful concept that we should adopt a primitive or Millian account. It further follows if autonomous decisions needn’t be good decisions that if we lie to a mature adult in order to protect him from a bad decision that we are failing to respect his autonomy. I would suggest accepting the above has implications for apology. Insincere apology is a form of lying. Perhaps in most circumstance apologising without really mean it is a form of white lying. Nonetheless such apologising just compounds any wrong by showing a lack of any real respect to the one lied to.
I have argued that it is always wrong to lie if this means we fail to respect someone’s autonomy even this is done for beneficent reasons. The question now arises is lying ever acceptable? If the mother of a young child who pesters her to buy another ice cream lies then her lie can be justified. The child isn’t autonomous yet and having two ice creams isn’t in her best interests. However caution is needed if we accept a primitive account of autonomy as I suggested above then slightly older children who are capable of making autonomous decisions and lying to them fails to respect their autonomy. Sam Harris uses an extreme example and asks should we lie even if with “Nazis at the door and Anne Frank is in the attic”. Of course we should lie. We should lie to protect Anne Frank and her autonomy. Lying to someone who is infringing someone else’s autonomy is perfectly acceptable, lying to protect autonomy is lying to respect autonomy.
What conclusions can be drawn from the above? Firstly we should never
lie if this means failing to respect autonomy even if our lies might be in what
we consider to be someone’s best interests. Even white lies are wrong. Secondly
if autonomy is to remain a meaningful concept we must always give precedence to
respecting autonomy over acting beneficently. Lastly lying to autonomous agents
can never be kind.
Wednesday, 21 August 2019
Different Degrees or Different Types of Rape?
Wednesday, 19 June 2019
The Logic of Relieving Suffering and Voluntary Euthanasia
- Silver D, (2003) Lethal Injection, Autonomy and the proper ends of Medicine, Bioethics 17(2), pp. 205-211.
Wednesday, 22 May 2019
Redesigning People
- Danaher, Mcarthur, and Migotti, 2017 Robot Sex: Social and Ethical Implications, MIT Press
- Ingmar Persson & Julian Savulescu, 2012, UNFIT FOR THE FUTURE, Oxford University Press.
Thursday, 11 April 2019
A right to anaesthesia, a right to physician euthanasia?
In an editorial in Anaesthesia Julian Savulescu and Janet
Radcliffe‐Richards
suggest that many people who are against the deliberate killing of terminally
ill patients who wish to die should have no objection to what is known as
terminal sedation, bringing about unconsciousness for terminally ill patients until
their natural death, see Anaesthesia . I agree with
Savulescu and Radcliffe‐Richards
that most people would accept that sedation for terminally ill patients is not wrong
when death is imminent. In France in 2016 a law came into effect granting
terminally ill patients the right to anaesthesia until death. Sinmyee
et al go further and argue that a right to anaesthesia should be available
to all patients who choose to end their life by starvation or dehydration, see Sinmyee
. Would most people accept that sedation for terminally ill patients is not
wrong when death is inevitable but not imminent? Perhaps a patient has a
prognosis that he has only six months to live. Secondly would most people accept
that sedation for terminally ill patients is not wrong when used to relieve suffering
which they cause themselves by a refusal to eat or to drink? I’m not sure what
most people would find acceptable in either of these scenarios. In this posting
I will firstly briefly summarise the argument why it isn’t morally wrong to
sedate terminally ill patients even if their current suffering is due caused by
a refusal to eat or drink. I will then consider what implications accepting
this argument has for accepting physician assisted suicide and voluntary
euthanasia.
Let us accept that any competent person has right to refuse
to take food and water. It might be objected that in some cases the person in
question is unlikely to be competent due to eating disorders such as anorexia.
However clearly this objection doesn’t carry much weight when considering
terminally ill patients. Let us also accept that relieving pain is a legitimate
end of medicine even when this lessens a patient’s life span. Let us still further
accept that relieving pain remains a legitimate end of medicine even when this
pain is due to self-harm. We treat drug users for their addiction. Lastly let
us accept that if pain cannot be controlled by any other means that it can be
controlled by deep sedation. It appears to follow that deeply sedating a
patient suffering from a terminal illness, even if his immediate suffering is
caused by his refusal to eat or drink, is a legitimate end of medicine. It
follows that in these circumstances deep sedation would not be morally wrong.
Let us now consider how permanent deep sedation differs
from death. For a dead person conscious life is over. Conscious life is also
over anyone who will be deeply sedated until he dies. Of course for someone who
is deeply sedated some important unconscious physiological processes such as
breathing will continue. The same is not true of the dead. But do these
unconscious physiological processes matter if someone will never resume
consciousness or take part in life again? If they do matter who do they matter
to? These unconscious physiological processes certainly don’t matter to the sedated
person. If they doesn’t matter to the person involved why should they matter
morally to others? It would appear to follow that there is no significant moral
difference between being dead and being deeply sedated until death. If this is
so is there any moral difference between a doctor deeply sedating someone until
he dies and helping him die a good death if he requests help to do so? If
dying and being deeply sedated until death are equivalent for moral concerns then
we should be prepared to conclude that if we are prepared to accept deep
sedation until death that we should be prepared to accept physician assisted
suicide PAS.
It might be objected that deep sedation involves no suffering
whilst helping a patient to die might do so. However even if we accept this
objection the above question might be reframed. Is there any moral difference
between a doctor deeply sedating someone until he dies and deeply sedating
someone prior to carry out his previously expressed wishes for voluntary euthanasia?
If
there isn’t any difference then we should be prepared to conclude that if we
are prepared to accept deep sedation until death that we should be prepared to
accept voluntary euthanasia, which might require prior sedation, when requested
by a terminally ill patient.
I now want to examine two major objections to the above
conclusion. Firstly it might be objected that the above argument depends on the
concept of a person and that when considering deep sedation and voluntary euthanasia
we should consider human beings instead. My objector might argue that that
matters is not whether a person continues to exist bur whether a human being
continues to exist. What does it mean for a human being to continue existing?
Is someone who will never regain consciousness but for whom unconscious
physiological processes such as breathing continue still a human being? My
objector might conclude the answer is obvious and is affirmative. However if we
consider the concept of brain death commonly used in transplant medicine the
answer is not obvious. Someone is brain dead if he has a permanent absence of cerebral
and brainstem functions, however mechanical ventilators and other advanced
critical care services can maintain unconscious physiological processes such as
breathing for some time. Whether someone who is brain dead remains a human
being is far from obvious for we can use his organs for transplant subject to
consent. Why does brain death matter? It matters not simply because of a loss
of cerebral and brainstem functions but because the implications of these
losses. These losses lead to a permanent loss of consciousness. If the above is
accepted then substituting human for persons doesn’t affect my original
argument.
I now want to consider a second objection to my argument
that if we are prepared to accept deep sedation of the terminally ill patients
until death that we should also be prepared to voluntary euthanasia for such patients.
It might be objected that I have slipped too easily from considering PAS to
considering voluntary euthanasia and that the two aren’t equivalent. PAS is
self-administered whilst voluntary euthanasia is carried out by a physician. I
made this move because it has been suggested that PAS might involve suffering
by the terminally ill patient. As a philosopher I am unable to say much about whether
PAS might involve suffering. However I can say something about the possible
scenarios. Firstly if PAS doesn’t necessarily involve suffering then my original
conclusion stands. Next let us assume that PAS involves some limited suffering.
In this scenario it might be questioned whether a terminally ill patient needs
to be fully anaesthetised for PAS to take place? Perhaps a patient’s pain might
be alleviated without affecting his cognitive abilities allowing him to carry
out PAS. Once again my original conclusion stands. Lastly let us assume that
PAS involves suffering that cannot be fully alleviated without full anaesthesia.
In this scenario PAS isn’t possible with full pain relief. In this scenario the
question changes and becomes, if we are prepared to accept deep sedation until
death then why shouldn’t we be prepared to accept voluntary euthanasia?
In order to answer the above question I want to consider
two further scenarios. In both scenarios I will assume the patient is fully
competent. In the first I will assume that the patient is capable of initiating
the start of his anaesthesia before his physician takes over and delivers a
fatal dose. In this scenario why is the patient initiating his own anaesthesia?
I would suggest he isn’t only initiating a form of pain relief. He is only initiating
pain relief in order to die. In this scenario the patient’s actions resemble
those of a patient undergoing PAS.
However the two are not identical. In PAS the physician only supplies
the means and need not be present at the time of death whilst in the above
scenario the physician must not only be present but also deliver the lethal
dose. Let us accept that the physician’s presence or lack of it is not relevant
morally. However we must ask ourselves whether the fact that the physician
supplies the means of dying differs in a morally significant way from the
physician applying the lethal dose. It might be suggested that this a case in
which we could use the principle of double effect to explain the difference. I
would be reluctant to accept this suggestion. When supplying the means to die
the physician involved in PAS has the intention of allowing the patient to kill
himself, it isn’t a foreseen consequence of something else. The physician’s
intention is the same whether he is involved in PAS or voluntary euthanasia as
described in the above scenario. It seems provided the patient involved is able
to initiate his own anaesthesia that there is no morally significant difference
between voluntary euthanasia in these circumstances and PAS. Let us now
consider a second scenario in which the patient is unable to initiate his own
anaesthesia. I would suggest that there are no morally significant differences
between a physician carrying out voluntary euthanasia on a terminally ill
patient in this scenario and a physician suppling him with the means to carry
out PAS provided the degree of voluntariness is the same in both cases. However
is the degree of voluntariness the same in both cases? In the case of PAS the
patient’s intentions seem to be clear because he initiates the dying process.
If a patient can initiate his own anaesthesia I have argued he is initiating
his death and once again his intentions seem clear cut. However if a patient is
unable to initiate his own anaesthesia his intentions aren’t quite so clear
cut. Perhaps this situation can be remedied by a rigorous consent process and a
clear last directive. None the less differences remain between this scenario
and the one in which the patient initiates his own anaesthesia and for this
reason I would be reluctant to conclude that the scenario in which the patient
is unable to initiate his own anaesthesia is equivalent to PAS. The above
suggests some consequences for the process of deep sedation. Let us accept that
the deep sedation of terminally ill patients who are unable to initiate their
own sedation and voluntary are equivalent. It follows if we aren’t prepared to
accept voluntary euthanasia we shouldn’t be prepared to accept deep sedation if
the patient is unable to initiate his own anaesthesia.
In this posting I have argued that the deep sedation of
terminally ill patients should be morally acceptable. I further argued such
sedation was a legitimate use of medical skills. I have also assumed that most
people would find such sedation acceptable and less contentious than either PAS
or voluntary euthanasia. If most people find PA and voluntary euthanasia
unacceptable and deep sedation is a legitimate use of medical skills then such
sedation should be an option for the terminally ill. I then examined the moral
implications of accepting deep sedation. The main implications of this
acceptance are summarised below.
- If we are prepared to accept deep sedation for terminally ill patients until death then we should be prepared to accept PAS when this process does not involve suffering.
- If we are prepared to accept deep sedation until death and PAS involves some suffering then we should accept PAS provided that this suffering can be controlled without anaesthesia.
- If we are prepared to accept deep sedation until death and a patient is able to initiate his own anaesthesia then in these circumstances we should be prepared to accept voluntary euthanasia.
- If we are not prepared to accept voluntary euthanasia then we should not be prepared to accept deep sedation until death when a patient is unable to initiate his own anaesthesia.
Engaging with Robots
In an interesting paper Sven Nyholm considers some of the implications of controlling robots. I use the idea of control to ask a different...
-
In his posting on practical ethics Shlomit Harrosh connects the rights of death row inmates in certain states of the USA to choose the met...
-
According to Max Wind-Cowie shame should be liberated rather than legislated for. By this I take Wind-Cowie to mean that shame should pl...
-
Kristjan Kristjansson argues too much attention is paid to promoting an individual’s self esteem and not enough to promoting his self res...