In this posting I want to consider the topic of informed consent. Eric Chwang is interested in the difference between the standard needed for consent to be considered valid for normal clinical patients and the standard necessary for valid consent from research subjects (1). In this posting my sole concern is with normal patients. Chwang takes as his starting point the judgement in Canterbury v Spence, see Canterbury v Spence . This Judgement has two main strands. First the information a doctor must give a patient should be determined by the patient’s needs. The second condition places a restriction on these needs. Chwang calls the second condition the pragmatic criterion and expresses it as follows,
“in
order for consent to be valid, whether some piece of information needs to be
disclosed depends on whether it might affect the patient’s (subject’s) decision
whether to consent.” (2
)
The
pragmatic condition seems to reflect the judgement in the Montgomery
case . In this case the court held that doctors must ensure patients are
fully aware of any and all risks that an individual patient, not just the
risks mainstream medical practice, might consider significant. It is the
consequences of accepting the information requirements of this judgement I want
to explore in this posting.
The
pragmatic criterion gives us some guidance as to how much information a patient
should be supplied with in order to make a competent decision. Unfortunately,
this guidance seems to be at odds with the idea of informed consent being based
on respect for patient autonomy. Suppose a patient simply understands he is
likely to die without treatment and makes a decision on solely this basis, if
any additional information will not alter his decision then according to the
pragmatic criterion it is unnecessary to disclose any additional information.
Chwang writes,
“Suppose
that the only way to save my life is by amputation. To get consent for ‘life
saving treatment’, but without also mentioning that the treatment in question
is amputation, would be grossly inappropriate” (3).
The
question I will now discuss is what is inappropriate about obtaining consent in
this way? In order to help in this discussion I will use an example provided by
Steve Clarke.
“Consider
the case of ‘Squeamish John’. Squeamish John cannot bear to hear the details of
medical procedures; hearing these make him feel weak at the knees and
dramatically diminishes his capacity to make sensible decisions. Nevertheless
he does not wish to abrogate responsibility for his decision about whether or
not to undergo an operation. Squeamish John wishes to participate in a
restricted informed consent process in order to make his decision. He wishes to
make a decision based only on the disclosure of the risks and benefits of the
operation couched in cold, impersonal, statistical language. He does not wish
to have any significant details of the procedure described to him.” (4).
Let
us assume John gives consent in manner outlined by Clarke and he wakes minus
one leg. Chwang would find this situation grossly inappropriate and according
to the Montgomery judgement John’s would have given inadequate consent. I now
want to consider is inappropriate or inadequate about such a decision. I will now
argue what is inappropriate or inadequate about such a decision is not that it
is an non autonomous one. Let it be accepted an autonomous decision is simply a
decision with which the agent identifies himself and ‘cares about’; in this
context I am using ‘cares about’ in the same way as it is used by Harry
Frankfurt (5). If autonomy is defined in such a manner John’s decision appears
to be autonomous. However, some objector might argue for any decision to be
autonomous it must be made using practical reason. Even if this objection is
accepted it might be argued that practical reason is closely tied to an agent’s
identity and what he cares about. David Velleman for instance believes
practical reason is defined by the self-understanding someone gains by playing
himself (6). This understanding depends on him doing what makes sense or seems
appropriate to him; he must identify with and care about such actions. However,
my objector might respond further by arguing this isn’t normally how we use the
term practical reason. She might argue that anyone using practical reason to
make a decision should objectively weigh up all of her available options
connected to this decision. Any decision made this way would satisfy the
Montgomery judgement.
For
the sake of argument let us assume that assume practical reason does involve
some objective weighing up of all the relevant costs and benefits and that for a
decision to be autonomous it must utilise practical reason as so defined.
However, if we accept the above it follows that squeamish John’s cannot make an
autonomous decision. In this situation John’s squeamishness means his preferred
way of making his consent decision is the only possible way he can make a
decision. In everyday life outside a medical context all of us sometimes
delegate important decisions to experts of our choice, such as lawyers or
financial advisors, without others questioning our autonomy. Are then doctors
any less trustworthy than lawyers or financial advisors? It seems obvious to me
that they are not. Does then the context in which informed consent takes place
differ from other contexts such as the law and finance in respect of an agent’s
ability to make autonomous decisions? I would suggest it does not. It follows
if squeamish John is permitted to make a decision in the way he prefers it
would be an autonomous decision. It further follows what Chwang finds
inappropriate, or the Montgomery judgement finds inadequate, about such a
decision is not that it is a non-autonomous one.
I
have argued squeamish John’s proposed decision would be an autonomous one. I
would suggest what Chwang finds grossly inappropriate or the Montgomery
judgement inadequate about such a decision is either that it is not a good
decision or a good way to make such a decision. I would argue we should not
equate autonomous decisions with good decisions. Autonomous decisions are
simply autonomous decision and not autonomous decisions plus another
requirement. Autonomous decisions as defined above need not of necessity good
decisions. None the less autonomous decisions cannot simply be made at random,
by the throw of a dice for instance. Autonomous decisions must be made on the
basis of some information. If it is accepted that autonomous
decisions need not of necessity be good decisions then the amount of
information necessary to make an autonomous decision may not always be
identical with the amount of information needed to make a good decision.
The above raises the question about how much information is needed to make an
autonomous decision?
In
order to answer the above question, we must first be clear about an agent’s
purpose when making an autonomous decision. I have suggested above an
autonomous decision is one which the agent ‘cares about’ and with he identifies
with. This type of decision is one the agent is wholehearted about. Frankfurt
argues a wholehearted decision is one with which the agent is satisfied with.
He further argues satisfaction involves an absence of restlessness and any
desire for change (7). It is of course true that many agents would not be
satisfied with any decision they regarded as sub optimal. However, it would
appear a decision need not be an optimal decision for it to be an autonomous one
according to Frankfurt. All that is necessary for a decision to be autonomous
is that the agent is satisfied with his decision. I accept such a position. My
objector might again point out such decisions need not be rational ones and
that any decision lacking rationality should not be regarded as a fully autonomous
one. In reply I would question exactly what is meant by rational. I will assume
in the context of giving consent rationality refers to practical rationality.
If this is so I would once reiterate that some philosophers such as Velleman
would regard decisions with which the agent is satisfied with as defined above
or finds appropriate as practically rational. In addition, I would argue such
decisions are examples of satisficing or bounded rationality. The term
satisficing was introduced by Herbert Simon in 1956. Satisficing does not
require an agent maximise his good. Satisficing only requires that an agent
brings about an outcome that he considers good enough by some standard. My
objector might now point an autonomous agent needs only to be satisfied with
his decision and does not set some standard by which any option must be judged.
She might then argue any such decisions are not examples of bounded
rationality. In reply I would suggest satisfaction as defined above must at the
very least involve some unconscious bounds and that autonomous decisions
implicitly involve bounded rationality. It follows the amount of
information needed for an agent to make an autonomous decision is the amount of
information that would satisfy agent.
I
have used the example of squeamish John to show in certain contexts, provided
the only way to save someone’s life is by amputation and consent is obtained
without mentioning this fact, that none the less the patient’s consent might be
autonomous. Chwang believes such consent would be grossly inappropriate.
Chwang’s belief seems to be based on the idea that the patient has been
inadequately informed. I believe Chwang is correct in most contexts but not
all. Good quality consent should be an aim of the informed consent process,
see GMC guidance for consent . However, the taking of consent like
medical interventions does not always occur under ideal conditions and in some
contexts good quality consent may be impossible. The General Medical Council’s
guidelines on consent of 1998 specifically stated that the purpose of consent
was to respect patient autonomy. The current guidelines mentioned above do not
explicitly base informed consent on respect for autonomy but none the less
implicitly require this respect. If respect for autonomy is the sole principle
on which informed consent is based then we must simply respect all autonomous
decisions. My objector might point the purpose of medicine is to act
beneficently towards patients. She might then use this fact to argue basing
informed consent solely on respect for autonomy is simplistic. She might then
suggest the purpose of informed consent should be to respect patient
autonomy and enable them to make good decisions. I
accept the above is the ideal which informed consent should aim for. However,
in some contexts acting beneficently might clash with respecting patient
autonomy. Such a clash must be resolved. I have previously suggested we cannot
act truly beneficently if we fail to respect autonomy. We must give priority to
respecting autonomy over acting beneficently when these values clash, see Autonomy and acting Beneficently. Accepting the above means we must in some
situations accept less than ideal decisions provided these decisions are
autonomous and that Chwang is mistaken to regard such decisions as
inappropriate in these situations.
Lastly
I want to consider whether a consequence of accepting the pragmatic criterion
is accepting the concept of asymmetric competence. This concept is defined by
Wilks as follows.
“If
we consider a safe, routine treatment for an acute and dangerous condition (as
with an appendectomy for appendicitis), it is clear that the risk in accepting
the treatment is small, the benefit great, while the risk in refusing it is
great and the benefit in most cases non existent. This means that one
confronted with this choice would require a higher level of competence to say
no than to say yes, with, indeed, a very pronounced difference between the
levels” (8)
Intuitively
the pragmatic criterion supports Wilks’ position. In the situation such as that
envisioned by Wilks above if a patient consents a great deal of information is
unlikely to alter his decision. However, were he to refuse to consent some
additional information might well alter his decision. Before considering the
question of asymmetric competence I will examine two related concepts. I will
examine the asymmetric triggering of competence assessments and the asymmetry
in information needed to give competent consent and to give a competent
refusal. I will firstly argue that for pragmatic reasons there should be
asymmetric triggering of competence assessments. Indeed, it seems unlikely any
patient’s competence will be questioned provided his consent is sought and he
consents. I would support this failure to assess competence only in situations
in which there is universal agreement among health professionals that some
particular treatment is in a patient’s best interests. I have argued the most
important purpose of patient consent is to protect patient autonomy. The reason
why competence is sometimes assessed is to ensure non-autonomous patients
receive beneficent care. In the light of the above assessing a patient’s
competence if he consents seems unnecessary. Provided the patient is competent
his autonomous decision should be respected. However, if he was assessed as
incompetent and a surrogate decision maker made a decision on his behalf then
any treatment would identical with the treatment he had previously consented
to. It follows no useful purpose is served by assessing a patient’s
competence provided he consents to some treatment when the health benefits are
clear and the risks of non-treatment great.
I
will now argue there is an asymmetry in the information needed for a patient to
make a competent decision when he consents and when he refuses to consent. Let
it be accepted as I have argued above any autonomous decision must count as a
competent decision. Let us consider squeamish John once again. John consents to
treatment and is satisfied with his decision. It might be suggested the reason
why John is satisfied is that he finds the decision is appropriate to him
because he can justify it to himself. John can justify his decision by trusting
his doctors to do what is in his best interests. The minimal amount of
information John receives also satisfies the pragmatic criterion as any
additional information will not alter his autonomous decision. It follows as I
have argued above John can make a competent decision, even if less than an
ideal one, based on the minimal information provided. Now let us consider a
situation in which a patient refuses to consent and insists on only being
supplied with the same minimal information available to John. In this
situation, provided the patient’s condition is non-life threatening, the
procedure would simply be cancelled and the patient’s competence would remain
unquestioned. For example a patient who refuses to consent to a hip
replacement. However, let us assume the patient’s condition is life
threatening. In this situation I would argue such a patient cannot make an
autonomous decision and hence is not competent to give consent. There might be
one exception to the above. A suicidal patient may well have enough information
to make an autonomous decision. Needless to say medicine is not in the business
of helping patients commit suicide with the possible exception of those who are
terminally ill. The reason why such a patient cannot make an autonomous
decision is he does not have enough information to make a decision with which
he can be satisfied; a decision that he can justify to himself. In addition any
additional information may well alter the patient’s decision meaning the information
provided in this situation does not satisfy the pragmatic criterion. It follows
if we accept either that a competent decision must be autonomous one or one
requiring that a competent patient has enough information to satisfy the
pragmatic criterion that a patient in this situation cannot make a competent
decision. It further follows there is sometimes an asymmetry in the
information a patient needs to make a competent decision if he consents and the
information he needs if he refuses to consent.
Let
it be accepted asymmetry between the information a patient needs when he
consents and refuses consent. It is then possible for a patient to be
asymmetrically competent. If a patient can understand the information needed to
consent but fails to understand the additional information needed to refuse
consent then he is asymmetrically competent. In practice I believe this
situation is unlikely to occur as it seems to me most patients will be capable
of understanding the additional information.
- Eric Chwang, 2010, A Puzzle about Consent, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27(3).
- Chwang, page 262.
- Chwang, page 265.
- Steve Clarke, 2001, Informed Consent in Medicine in Comparison with Consent with Consent in Other Areas of Human Activity, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39, page 177
- Harry Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love, Cambridge University Press
- David Vellman, 2009, How We Get Along, Cambridge University Press, page 18.
- Frankfurt, 1999, page 103.
- Wilks, 1997, The debate over Risk-related Standards of competence, Bioethics 11(5), page 417., 2010, A Puzzle about Consent, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27(3)..