- Ludwig Wittgenstein, 1953, Philosophical Investigations, Blackwell, 65.
- Danaher John, 2019, Automation and Utopia, Harvard University, page 231
- Danaher, page 234
- Bennett Helm, 2010 Love, Friendship & the Self, Oxford University Press
- Gwen Bradford, 2015, Achievement, Oxford University Press
- Danaher, chapter 7.
This blog is concerned with most topics in applied philosophy. In particular it is concerned with autonomy, love and other emotions. comments are most welcome
Thursday, 18 June 2020
Games, Sport and Drugs
Wednesday, 20 May 2020
Coronavirus Passports
The Covid-19 pandemic lockdown has caused great damage to the way people lead their lives and the economy. It is in the interests of both society and individuals to lift the lockdown. One way this might be done would be by the issuing of covid-19 immunity passports. According to Olivia Kates the path to reopening public life should be set by expert health officials, with close attention to justice and equity, and at no point on that path should anyone be stopped and asked, “Show me your passport”, see Hastings Center . In this posting I want to argue that the introduction of covid-19 passports would be fair in certain circumstances should be accepted.
What conditions would need to be satisfied before we could consider the introduction of covid-19 immunity passports? Firstly if a fully tested vaccine became available which offered a high degree of protection and that those vaccinated couldn’t pass on the virus to others. If this condition is meet then it would be feasible to introduce a covid-19 passport. Secondly if it is ascertained that those who have had covid-19 have develop antibodies which protect them from reinfection for a reasonable period of time. In addition a test must have been developed which can tell whether someone has acquired these antibodies. If either of these conditions can be meet then it would also be feasible to introduce a covid-19 passport for a limited period dependent on how long the immunity lasts.
What reasons can be advanced for the introduction of these passports? Firstly it should allow passport holders greater freedom to go to the places they want because they won’t pass the virus on to others and won’t become a burden on our health services. Secondly if the number of passport holders was large enough this might help revive society and the economy quicker without risking another peak of infections. In certain settings social distancing isn’t feasible. For instance when eating out or going to the theatre or attending large sporting events. If during the pandemic only passport holders were able go to restaurants, to attend the theatre or large sporting events then perhaps these place could benefit. Lastly let us assume that an effective vaccine becomes widely available. In these circumstances the extreme pressure on society and the economy might lead some to propose mandatory vaccination. In these circumstances covid-19 passports might relieve this pressure whilst causing less damage to personal autonomy. In light of the above reasons exist for the introduction of covid-19 passports.
Let us assume that an effect vaccine becomes available. Let us also assume that the vaccine will be made available to all. In these circumstances would we still have reasons to introduce corona virus passports? I will now argue that we have two reasons to introduce passports. Firstly any vaccination will take time. The introduction of passports might enable restaurants, sporting venues and theatres to reopen earlier than would be possible otherwise. Such earlier reopening would benefit the institutions involved and permit greater freedom to passport holders. Secondly some people such as anti-vaxxers might not want to become vaccinated and passports would offer an incentive to do so. It would appear that even with the advent of an effective corona virus vaccine that we still have reasons for a temporary introduction of passports. What reasons can be advanced for their non-introduction?
First it might be argued that covid-19 passports would lead to a divided society, those who have passports and those who don’t. It might then be argued a divided society is a bad society. A divided society need not be a bad society unless this division is unfair. If the purpose of covid-19 passports only benefits passports holders then it might be argued that non-passport holders are being treated unfairly because they are being denied the benefits available to passport holders. Clearly passport holders might benefit from their passports by being able to engage more fully in society. For instance they may work where social distancing is impossible, travel more widely and attend the theatre. However even if passports enable the holders to enjoy these benefits they don’t deny these benefits to non-passport holders. If everyone during the pandemic wasn’t able to work where social distancing was impossible, travel widely and attend the theatre then these jobs would cease, widespread travel would be impossible and theatres would remain closed. Driving licences benefit those who hold them by allowing them to drive on public roads but such licences, passports, don’t seem to be unfair on those who don’t hold them. Fairness isn’t simply about benefitting people equally it is about benefitting people equally when this is possible. I would suggest the above would hold even if supplies of vaccine are limited provided these supplies are allocated fairly. If supplies are limited are fairly allocated then passports could benefit those who are vaccinated but limited supplies mean others couldn’t benefit so the question of fairness doesn’t arise.
The above argument is based on the premise that a divided society is a bad society only when it is an unfair society. Some might reject this premise. They might argue that a divided society creates envy, jealousy and anger and these unhealthy emotions lead to an unhealthy society. Those who don’t have passports become envious and jealous of those who do. Let us accept that we should do our best to mitigate these emotions this isn’t the same as eliminating the cause of these emotions. Let us also accept that it is wrong to disable someone to benefit others. The introduction of covid-19 passports would enable some people to avail themselves of some benefits. I would suggest that preventing someone from enabling himself is a form of disablement and hence wrong. For instance denying someone education which would enable him to better himself would be a kind of disablement. I would further suggest that a divided society is a better society than any society which considers disabling some of its members.
It might be objected that my argument is flawed. It is
flawed because my suggestion that, preventing someone from enabling himself is
a form of disablement, is too simplistic. My objector might then suggest that
enabling is a form of enhancement. I am prepared to accept his objection. I
accept that there is a difference between someone enhancing himself and being
enhanced. There is a difference between someone having the capacity to enhance
oneself and being enhanced by being given the capacity to enhance oneself. For
instance there is a difference between someone enhancing himself by learning
and being enhanced by pharmacological means. In one case the capacity to
enhance oneself is already present, in the other it is introduced. With these
differences in mind I accept, for the purposes of this argument, that preventing
someone from being enabled by being given additional capacities isn’t a form of
disablement. However I would still suggest that preventing someone from
exercising some capacity which he already possesses is a form of disablement. I
would further suggest that banning covid-19 passports which would enable some
people to avail themselves of some benefits falls into the latter group and as
a result is a form of disablement. Accepting the above means even if the
introduction of covid-19 passports leads to a more divided society this doesn’t
mean it would be wrong to do so.
I have argued that it would be morally permissible to
introduce covid-19 passports in two scenarios. However this is an applied
philosophy blog and the question must be asked would their issue be useful.
Issuing such passports would only be useful if it both opened up society whilst
at the same time controlling the infection. Let us accept that the issue of
civid-19 passports would open up society. However would their issue be
effective in preventing another peak in infection? Their effectiveness might be
undermined by two factors, the presence of fakes and a lack of proper scrutiny.
I would argue the problem of fakes is unlikely to undermine the passports
effectiveness. After all fake driving licences and normal passports exist but
these don’t cause major difficulties. Perhaps the introduction of some
government approved app might reduce this risk. The problem of a lack of
scrutiny is more difficult. Scrutiny in workplaces shouldn’t be difficult but
the same wouldn’t be true of the entrances to theatres and sporting events. At
such events time pressure might lead to a lack of proper scrutiny. However once
again the introduction of an effective app might reduce this danger.
Friday, 1 May 2020
Locking Down the Elderly
Thursday, 23 April 2020
Inner Virtue and Private Racist Thoughts
In this posting I want to consider Nicolas Bommarito’s idea of inner moral virtue. In doing so I want to examine whether our purely private thoughts matter morally. For instance someone might have private evil thoughts but never express or act on them. In order to make the idea of inner moral virtue clear I will combine my examination with considering whether someone’s purely private racist’s thoughts are wrong and if so why. The thoughts I will be considering will be purely private conscious thoughts which the thinker endorses to some degree rather than simply some unconscious bias.it might be thought that the question of private inner thoughts is interesting but of little importance. However is someone who has private evil thoughts evil even if he never expresses or acts on them perhaps because hr fears punishment? If not do we have to accept that we can force people to be good and that morality doesn’t have an inner component.
Let us start our investigation by considering Galen
Strawson’s idea of weather watchers (1). Bommarito describes these as follows,
iant stone monoliths, they are living creatures with mental lives much like our own—own—they have thoughts, memories, desires, emotions, sensations, and even fantasies and dreams. These creatures care very deeply about the weather; they are filled with joy when it is sunny out and melancholy when it rains or snows. Because of their physiology, they are completely incapable of any behavioral action……However, none of their rich mental lives are externally observable and, because of the kind of creatures they are, they are unable to perform overt actions of any kind….. They will even lack the associated intentions.” (2)
It might be objected that the idea of weather watchers is of little moral relevance because they are pure fantasy. However there are human beings who share many of the characteristics of weather watchers, those suffering from locked in syndrome. Someone with locked in syndrome may be happy when he has visitors, unhappy when he hasn’t and dream about having visitors when he is alone in the night. Clearly the mental life of someone with locked in syndrome matters to him but does his purely mental life have any moral relevance
Traditionally moral virtue is linked to character and some someone can be said to be virtuous if he has a disposition or attitudes which cause him to act morally most of the time. Clearly a weather watcher cannot be virtuous in this traditional sense because traditionally being virtuous is connected to action. However Bommarito argues that an inability to act does not preclude someone from having inner moral virtue linked to character. What does Bommarito mean by an inner moral virtue or vice? He argues that whilst weather watchers are incapable of virtue in the traditional sense that nonetheless they are capable of some sort of inner virtue or vice. A Weather Watcher who took pleasure in knowing that another of his kind was experiencing pleasure in the warm sun might be said to be expressing inner virtue. However schadenfreude shows such a definition is too simplistic. Someone might takes pleasure in another’s suffering. If someone else takes pleasure in the pleasure of the person enjoying schadenfreude then he cannot be regarded as being virtuous. Bommarito sees virtuous states as mental manifestations of an underlying moral concern. This definition could be seen as one part of the more traditional definition outlined above which sees someone as virtuous provided he has dispositions or attitudes which cause him to act morally most of the time, his dispositions can be seen as mental manifestations of an underlying moral concern. Accepting such a definition makes inner virtue a possibility. If a weather watcher takes pleasure in another watcher’s pleasure in the warm sun then he is being virtuous provided his pleasure is a manifestation of caring, of moral concern for the other. Similarly someone with locked in syndrome is being virtuous if he takes pleasure when his nurse hums happily to herself, his pleasure is a manifestation of concern for her wellbeing. It might be objected that these examples aren’t really manifestations of moral concern because they are concerned with happiness and someone’s happiness isn’t a moral concern. Two responses are possible to this objection. First someone’s happiness is connected to his wellbeing and someone’s wellbeing is a moral concern. Secondly inner virtue might be defined as manifestations of an underlying caring about someone’s wellbeing rather than moral concern. In the rest of this posting I will adopt this amended definition.
What are the consequences of accepting the above definition
for our intuitive ideas concerning virtue? Firstly if we accept the idea of
inner virtue then someone can be virtuous without acting. Someone with locked
in syndrome who is incapable of action can still be virtuous. However caution is needed here. In the above
definition I intentionally replaced Borramito’s ‘concern’ by ‘caring about’. I
did so to exclude someone, who is supposedly concerned about another’s wellbeing
and is capable of acting to promote this wellbeing but nonetheless fails to do
so from being regarded as virtuous. For instance a parent who is always
expressing concern for his children’s wellbeing but fails to attend parent’s
evenings, sporting and other events which matter to his children without a
genuine excuse. Someone cannot be said to care about the wellbeing of others if
he takes no steps to promote their wellbeing when he is able to do so. Secondly
it might be pointed out that inner virtue, the manifestation of an underlying
caring about someone’s wellbeing, is usually manifested by pleasure and that
pleasure is involuntary. It then might be argued that accepting the above
definition makes it hard to praise the virtuous and blame the vicious. It might
then be concluded that inner virtue isn’t a real virtue because acting
virtuously is usually regarded as praiseworthy. We can’t be praised or blamed
for things which are beyond our control. Two objections can be raised to this
argument. Firstly is more conventionally defined virtue always praiseworthy?
Consider a child from an affluent home with good loving parents who grows up to
be virtuous because of his background and parental encouragement. Is his virtue
praiseworthy? Perhaps we should regard virtue as something to be appreciated rather
than praised. We might say someone has a better character than someone
else even if he isn’t responsible for his better character and doesn’t deserve
to be praised for it. Secondly we might question how we acquire our sense of
pleasure. A baby just gets pleasure from certain things but do we acquire all
our pleasures in the same way? Do we have any input into our acquisition of
some pleasures? For instance if we enjoy classical music did we simply come to
enjoy it or does our will play some part in its acquisition? Do we have any
control over the maintenance of pleasures? For instance if classical music
pleases us we can maintain this pleasure by going to concerts. Do we have
higher pleasures based our lower pleasures? Being pleased or displeased about
what pleases us. If we have some limited control of some of the pleasures we
acquire then perhaps inner virtue and vice should attract some praise and
blame. Accepting either of the above arguments would mean inner virtue doesn’t
differ significantly from our more accepted ideas of virtue when it comes to
praise and blame.
now want to examine the broader consequences of accepting the idea of inner virtue. I will do so by considering inner virtue in conjunction with private racist thoughts. Racism is wrong but do someone’s unexpressed private racist thoughts do any harm and if so why? Clearly someone with locked in syndrome can have racist thoughts. Equally clearly these thoughts cannot be seen as manifestations of an underlying caring about someone’s wellbeing and if we accept that inner virtue is possible then these thoughts cannot be regarded as virtuous. Indeed I argue that such thoughts show a complete disregard for someone’s wellbeing and might be regarded as vicious. I now want to consider two questions. Firstly do the racist thoughts of someone with locked in syndrome do any harm? Secondly do purely private racist thoughts of someone who can act in the world do any harm?
If someone with locked in syndrome has racist thoughts then he harms no one else because he is incapable of action. It might then be argued that because his thoughts don’t harm others that these thoughts really don’t matter. However would we say that the alcoholism of a private alcoholic who drinks alone and doesn’t harms others doesn’t matter? I would suggest we wouldn’t. His alcoholism matters even if no one else becomes aware of it because he harms himself. It might be objected at this point that the analogy I’m trying to make is a false one because the alcoholic harms his physiological health whilst a racist with locked in syndrome doesn’t. In response I now want to argue that even if a racist with locked in syndrome doesn’t harm his physiological health that nonetheless his racist thoughts harm him by damaging his character. How might a private racist thoughts damage character? My argument will be based on two premises. My first premise is that caring about the welfare of others is a necessary condition for having a good character. Someone who is indifferent to the good of others might have some prudential virtues and be said to have a strong character but it cannot be said he has a good character. It might be objected that someone can have a good character and not care about the welfare of others. For instance he might believe in retributory justice and that some people deserve to suffer. In order to accommodate this objection I will amend the above premise slightly. This amended first premise holds that someone cannot be said to have a good character if he fails to care about the undeserved suffering of others. My second premise is that everyone cares about having a good character. It might be objected that my second premise is an extremely over optimistic one. Nonetheless I wish to defend it. It might now be objected that sadism shows my second premise to be unsound because a sadist clearly doesn’t care about having a good character. In response I would suggest even if a sadist happily enjoys inflicting pain on others and accepts his nature that nonetheless he still believes it would be better not to be a sadist. No one aspires to be a sadist. A sadist values having a good character even if he doesn’t value it enough to change his ways. Let us accept my second premise that everyone cares, at least to some degree, about having a good character. It follows that someone with locked in syndrome who has racist thoughts also cares about having a good character at least to some degree. If he has racist thoughts then these thoughts manifest a lack of caring for the underserved suffering of people of other races. It follows that his racist thoughts damages him, even if they don’t damage anyone else, by splitting his character even if this splitting is of no moral concern. Racist thoughts and the caring about character conflict. However even if we don’t accept my second premise I would still argue that someone who doesn’t care about having a good character damages his character. His character is damaged by a lack of aspiration to be a better person.
I now want to consider more practical matters. Does someone
who doesn’t have locked in syndrome but has purely private racist thoughts do
any real harm. Clearly as I have argued above he damages himself but are these
private thoughts of any moral concern provided that he doesn’t harm others?
Clearly a smoker damages his health but his smoking shouldn’t be of concern to
others if he is an adult and smokes in a field. It might then be argued by
analogy that if someone has private racist thoughts that these thoughts
shouldn’t be of concern to others. It might then be concluded that someone
could still act virtuously even if he has vicious private racist thoughts. What
does it mean to act virtuously? A
behaviourist account of virtue might suggest that someone acts virtuously
provided he acts in accordance with moral norms. If we accept such an account
then someone could act virtuously if his motive was purely to signal virtue or
even if his actions were the result of luck. If we aren’t prepared to accept
that actions based on virtue signalling or due to luck are truly virtuous ones
then we can’t accept a behaviourist account of virtue. Virtue isn’t a shallow
concept but has roots. These roots lie in someone’s disposition to act
virtuously most of the time. These dispositions are a result of, or form part
of someone’s character. It follows that acting virtuously is rooted in
character. We have defined inner virtue above as a manifestation of an
underlying caring about someone’s wellbeing. Let us accept that what we care
about is linked to our character. It follows that acting virtuously and inner
virtue are connected by character. I now want to argue that having private
racist thoughts harms someone by damaging his ability to act virtuously. Let us
assume that someone wants to act virtuously. I have argued above that if
someone wants to act virtuously that he must care about other people unless his
motive is purely to virtue signal in which case his actions aren’t virtuous.
Let us also assume that he has private racist thoughts. These thoughts manifest
a lack of concern for someone’s wellbeing. It follows that his character is
divided. This division matters because his purely private racist thoughts make
it harder for him to act virtuously. Even if someone’s purely private
thoughts are never made explicit they leak out into the world by making
behaving virtuously harder. This division matters for another reason. A racist
might have purely private racist thoughts which he never expresses but these
thoughts might leak out into the world by the way he acts, for instance in the
way he votes. It follows purely private racist thoughts should be of moral
concern. However accepting the above doesn’t make virtuous action completely
impossible. For instance someone might care about being slim and enjoy eating
junk food. His divided desires makes it harder for him to diet but not
impossible.
What conclusions can be drawn from the above? I have argued that our purely private thoughts matter. They matter because some of them are connected to inner virtue. Inner virtue is connected to acting virtuously because it is linked to character which in turn is determined by the things we care about. If the things we care about form a consistent set then it is easier to act virtuously. However it is harder to act virtuously if the things we care about form an inconsistent set and we are unable to rank our priorities. Acting virtuous isn’t just a matter of luck, it has roots which are connected to inner virtue. If morality has no roots then mimicking morality is the same as acting morally. Lastly if we are capable of acting in the world our inner virtues or vices are of moral concern because they leak out into the world by making it easier or more difficult it to act virtuously.
- Strawson, Galen. 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- Bommarito, Nicolas. 2017. Inner Virtue (Oxford Moral Theory) (pp. 13-14). Oxford University Press.
Monday, 23 March 2020
Stoicism, Covid-19 and Fortitude
Tuesday, 25 February 2020
Passive Aggression
In this posting I want to investigate the harm caused by
passive aggression. However there can also be some benefits of passive
aggression and these benefits must be weighed against any harm. In a previous
posting I argued that rudeness is harmful because it damages civil discourse. I
will attempt to show here that passive aggression is a form of rudeness and as
a result damages discourse. I will conclude that in most circumstance any
benefits of passive aggression are outweighed by the damage it does to civil
discourse. Before commencing my investigation I will examine what is meant by
passive aggression and the sort of circumstances in which it might be useful
and why.
What is meant by passive aggression? According to Rebecca
Roach passive aggression “is an expression of hostility,
resentment, contempt, etc, that are indirect.” Hostility, resentment and
contempt are all related to anger but it is important to note that acting with
passive aggression is not the same as expressing anger. Perhaps passive
aggression is a means of expressing repressed anger. Someone’s expression of
anger sometimes is also an attempt to elicit a response from those who have
angered him. Anger is connected to conflict. Passive aggression tries to avoid
conflict by limiting action. Pure anger is an emotion requiring no reflection
whilst the passive aggressor has to reflect on how he is going to react. Of
course passive aggression might be a manifestation of anger which is an emotion
but passive aggression remains a response to an emotion rather than the emotion
itself. Roach defines passive aggression as an expression of hostility,
resentment and contempt. It might then be argued that because hostility,
resentment and contempt are emotions that passive aggression is really a second
order emotion and that I am wrong to suggest otherwise. I would reject this
argument by suggesting even if hostility, resentment and contempt are emotion
passive aggression remains a reaction to these emotions rather than a higher
order emotion. Someone can be unemotional when reacting with passive
aggression. Lastly I will assume that passive aggression must be verbal because
otherwise sullenness could be regarded as a form of passive aggression. Some
might disagree with the last point but I won’t pursue it further here.
In what sort of circumstances is passive aggression usually
employed? I would suggest that these circumstances fall into two broad sets.
Firstly passive aggression is often employed when there is an asymmetry of
power making the expression of anger difficult.
For instance an office worker might employ passive aggression towards
his tyrannical boss. In these circumstances passive aggression is used because
civil discourse appears to be impossible. Secondly passive aggression might be
employed by someone who wishes to limit the damage full scale confrontation
might do to relationships but also wishes to register his displeasure about
someone else’s behaviour. These relationships are usually close relationships.
For instance Andrew’s partner Bernice fails to attend Andrew’s sister Clair’s
wedding due to some prior commitment. At a later date Clair says he can’t
attend the christening of Andrew and Bernice’s baby due to another prior
engagement. However had Bernice attended Clair’s wedding then Clair would have
been pleased to attend the christening. Clair wishes to register him
displeasure whilst at the same time avoiding a family row.
What harm does passive aggression cause? I will now argue
that passive aggression harms us in three ways. Firstly I have suggested above
that passive aggression is connected to hostility, resentment and contempt.
These are harmful emotions. By seeking to avoid conflict passive aggression
doesn’t address the issues underlying these emotions resulting in these issues
remaining unresolved and the associated harmful emotions retained to some
degree. It follows that passive aggression is harmful. Secondly it might be
argued that expressing anger sends a message to someone that something is
wrong. Repressed anger muddles the message. Expressing anger also focusses our
attention on addressing the wrong. Repressed would seem to be less effective in
doing so. However when there is an asymmetry of power even the expression
controlled anger is difficult. It might then be argued that in these
circumstance even if we can’t overtly express our anger that passive aggression
enables us to do so covertly. It follows that if passive aggression is the
covert expression of our underlying anger that expressing it might be of some
limited benefit to us by permitting some limited venting of our feelings. Thirdly
it might be argued that passive aggression might harm some people by causing a
sense of a loss of agency because they are unable to directly express
themselves. In response I would suggest that an asymmetry of power might causes
someone feel a loss of a sense of agency and that passive aggression might
benefit someone by restoring a limited sense of agency. Some sense of agency,
even a limited one, might benefit us more than simply adopting a sullen
attitude.
I have argued that passive aggression harms us because it
fails to address underlying issues which means we retain harmful emotions, it
fails to fully address the perceived wrong and damages agency. I then suggested
that the harm of passive aggression might be counterbalanced by allowing us to
covertly vent our anger leading to a reduction in the harmful emotions we are
experiencing and restore a limited sense of agency. It follows that on balance
passive aggression might benefit us. I now want to argue that passive
aggression harms us in another way by damaging civil discourse. First I will
argue that passive aggression is an indirect form of rudeness. Secondly I will
argue that rudeness damages discourse which causes harm.
What do we mean by rudeness? In a previous posting I
defined rudeness as someone knowingly not considering the needs, views and
wishes of another and at the time of this inconsideration the other being aware
of this inconsideration, see wooler.scottus
. If we adopt this definition then it isn’t immediately obvious than passive
aggression is a form of rudeness. After all passive aggression is triggered by
the views and wishes of others. However even if passive aggression is triggered
by the views and wishes of others it isn’t concerned with their needs. Passive
aggression is only concerned the views and wishes of others in a limited way,
it is only concerned with the perceived wrongness of these views. It follows
that someone expressing passive aggression fails to properly consider the
needs, views and wishes of the person the aggression is directed at. Must
someone at whom the aggression is aimed at be aware of the aggression? It might
be suggested that passive aggression is an indirect way of expressing
hostility, resentment and contempt those who the aggression is aimed need not
be aware of it. If this is so then passive aggression is simply a private
venting of feelings. I would reject the above suggestion as passive aggression
is only indirect aggression because the person expressing the aggression is
aware that the person at whom the aggression is aimed is aware of it. Passive
aggression is a way of making someone aware of your dissatisfaction with his
behaviour whilst at the same time trying to limit the damage done to your
relationship with him. In light of the above passive aggression seems to be a
form of rudeness.
I now want to briefly argue that rudeness harms someone by
damaging civil discourse. It might be argued that rudeness benefits the rude
person by enabling him to freely express his true feelings free from the
fetters of politeness. It might even be suggested that the free expression of
feelings means rudeness is connected to honesty, I would reject this second
suggestion because the focus of the rude person is partial and by knowingly
ignoring the views of others he might deprive himself of further knowledge of
the situation and increase the possibility of self-deception. However let us
accept that rudeness can benefit the rude person by simply allowing the
unfettered expression of his feelings. Unfortunately rudeness also involves an
inattention to the views of others and as a result damages discussion by
shifting the focus of our attention from the issues involved to the tone of the
discourse. Rudeness means we talk at each other rather than engage in a
meaningful civil discussion and fail to address the underlying long term
issues. Let us accept that civil discourse promotes the meaningful discussion
of difficult issues which benefits individuals. The pleasure of rudeness is
short lived whilst the resolution of difficult issues matters in the long term.
Issues that aren’t fully addressed can cause long term harm. It follows that
the short term pleasure of rudeness is outweighed by the long term damage it
does to individuals by a failure to address difficult issues. It further
follows that if passive aggression is a form of rudeness it harms us by
damaging discourse
It might be objected that in some circumstances civil
discourse isn’t possible. For instance if someone has a tyrannical employer
then he might be unable to engage in civil discourse about his grievances. In
other circumstances someone’s extreme sensitivity might make it difficult for
others to engage in meaningful discourse with him. In circumstances like these
the pleasure of passive aggression cannot be outweighed by the harm done to
civil discourse because civil discourse isn’t possible. Whilst being passively
aggressive makes no sense to the powerful it makes perfect sense to the
powerless. It follows that passive aggression might benefit some people in some
circumstances.
The above conclusion depends on the premise that in some
circumstances meaningful civil discourse is impossible. Let us accept this
premise. However even if we accept the premise if the above conclusion is to be
useful we must define these circumstance more rigidly. I argued above these
circumstances in which passive aggression might be useful fall into two broad
groups. Let us consider the first of these groups in which there is an
asymmetry of power. In a totalitarian regime such as Stalinist Russia discourse
about the regime’s policies is impossible and passive aggression might be
justified. Jokes at the regime’s expense might be regarded as a form of passive
aggression. However I would suggest that in most circumstances where there is
an asymmetry of power civil discourse isn’t impossible but merely difficult. I
would further suggest that just because civil discourse is difficult we
shouldn’t abandon it and fall back on passive aggression to relieve our
negative feelings. If we simply use passive aggression then we might be accused
of taking the easy option, mental laziness or being lacking in courage. We
might also be accused of failing to address the underlying issues which are the
cause our passive aggression. How might we engage in civil discourse when there
is an asymmetry of power? I would argue that this can be done in two ways.
Firstly we should ask those we are aggrieved with simply to confirm what we are
aggrieved about. This allows us to be sure our grievance is justified and may
also alert those who aggrieve us to the fact that we are aggrieved in a
non-confrontational way. Secondly we should ask those who aggrieve us why they
are acting this way. We ask them to justify their actions again in a
non-confrontational way. This might make those who aggrieve us reflect on their
actions. It might also give us reason to question our negative feelings. I have
argued elsewhere that such questioning can be repeated, see civil
discourse . However all conversations come to an end and if the
underlying issues cannot be resolved we should end the conversation by asking
the person who has aggrieved us does he really ‘mean that’. It follows in most
cases when there is an asymmetry of power civil discourse is possible even it
is difficult. It further follows that because passive aggression damages civil
discourse that we should try to avoid acting this way. Let us now consider the
second group of circumstances in which passive aggression is often employed.
These are when someone who wishes to limit the damage full scale confrontation
does to close relationships whilst at the same time registering him
displeasure. In these circumstances someone tries to limit the damage by
avoiding the full expression of his anger. However repressing anger doesn’t
eliminate it and it might manifest itself latter. I now want to argue that if
when we are aggrieved if we adopt the strategy outlined above of asking for
confirmation and then for further explanation then we shouldn’t do any greater
harm to relationships than we would by the use of passive aggression. Firstly
by simply asking someone to confirm something that aggrieves us might be
slightly annoying but doesn’t seem to be confrontational. Secondly asking
someone for an explanation might be confrontational to some degree but no more
so than employing passive aggression. It would appear that asking for
confirmation and explanation is no more confrontational than passive aggression
but has the additional benefit of addressing the underlying issues rather than
postponing discussion of them.
I have argued that passive aggression damages civil
discourse. I also argued that except in exceptional circumstances discourse is
possible when conducted carefully. I further argued that even if discourse is
difficult it is better to try and engage in meaningful discourse rather than
react with passive aggression because discourse helps resolve contentious
issues whilst passively aggressive merely postpones addressing them. Lastly I argued
that the use of passive aggression is a lazy way of dealing with contentious
issues. It follows that except in very limited circumstances we should avoid
the use of passive aggression.
Wednesday, 22 January 2020
Love me for a reason
Love is all around us, love matters to us and we value
loving and being loved, but why love matters so much to us isn’t immediately clear.
In this posting I want to offer a sketch of why love matters to us. Before
proceeding I must consider three question. Love has many variations, we can
have erotic love, parental love and affectionate love to name but a few. Are
these completely different types of love or have these variations all evolved
from a common basis or perhaps these apparently different types of love are in
reality different ways of expressing a general idea of love in different
domains?
According to Aristotle there are three types of love
erotic, philia and agape. If we accept Aristotle’s position then on first
appearance it would appear that there isn’t a single unified idea of love. According
to Aristotle erotic love is a passionate desire for another, usually a sexual
desire. Philia is more a fondness and appreciation of another and is important
in friendship. Agape refers to the love of God for man or man for God. However
it is still possible to argue that there is a unified concept of love. Firstly it
might be suggested that these types of love are in reality identical and that
the apparent differences in love might be due to the intensity of loving rather
than differences in type. Secondly it might be suggested that apparent differences
in love might be due to love being expressed differently in different domains.
It seems possible that a more modern version of agape might be that of
unconditional love of all. It follows that it is at least possible that there
is an underlying unified concept of love.
I now want to argue that there is indeed a unified
primitive concept of love. I will argue love isn’t just some concept that arose
recently or is limited to human beings. Let us that assume “caring about” is a
primitive form of loving. Animals can care about their offspring and if you
accept group selection, as Darwin did, then animals which care about their
offspring have an evolutionary advantage. It follows that a primitive type of love
has a very long history. However even if a plover’s behaviour when it pretends
to have a damaged wing in order to lure a predator away from its chicks is a
primitive form of love it isn’t what we usually mean by love. Perhaps Aristotle
was right after all and there are different types of love. I will now argue
that love has evolved some sort of structure rather than being differentiated
into different types. Let us accept us accept that many creatures including us
possess a primitive kind of love, the ability to “care about”. This basic form
of loving need have no affective or cognitive elements and might simply be
based on some on ancient neurochemical systems that evolved to serve our
ancestors' reproductive needs. It might be objected that such a basic system
isn’t what we mean by love. Love as we know it can’t be defined in such a basic
way. I accept my objectors point but my acceptance doesn’t mean we no longer
retain this basic system. Nature is parsimonious and doesn’t usually replace
ancient systems but adapts and modifies them to serve new purposes. It might
then be suggested that what we mean by love is this ancient primitive system of
“caring about” which has had its structure modified and built upon. It is hard
to see how such a simple structure could be modified so let us assume it has
been built upon. Firstly our primitive love has been expanded by our capacity
to feel empathy. Let us be clear what we mean by empathy. I don’t mean empathic
contagion such as that when one baby cries and another simply follows. I also don’t
mean the ability just to understand how another feels which can be exploited by
a sociopath. I mean having a disposition to feel as another feels. Secondly our
primitive love has been expanded by our increasing cognitive abilities. A bird
might only care for its chicks and perhaps its mate. Human beings increased
cognitive abilities enable them to see others as much the same as themselves
allowing them at the very least to question why they shouldn’t care about them
hence increasing love’s domain. Lastly our primitive love has been expanded by
the culture we live in. Let us accept that love can be regarded as an emotion.
According to Lisa Feldman Barrett,
“An emotion is your brain’s creation of what your bodily
sensations mean, in relation to what is going on around you in the world.” (1)
If we accept Feldman Barrett’s position then love depends
on concepts and our concepts are partly constructed by the culture we live in.
Her position can be supported by noticing that the dominant view of love in
culture has changed over the last hundred and fifty years from romantic love to
parental love. Let us accept that what we mean by love is our ancient capacity
to “care about” which has been built on and had its domain extended by our
capacity for empathy, our increased cognitive abilities and the culture we
inhabit.
Let us now consider why we value love as outlined above. We
can care about both loving and being loved. I now want to argue that loving is
more important than being loved. The above seems counterintuitive. However we
can imagine someone who isn’t loved but loves someone or something living a
meaningful even if somewhat unhappy life. We can’t imagine someone living a
meaningful life if she doesn’t care about anything at all. Let us assume that
we must “care about” our ideals. According to Frankfurt having ideals, “caring
about” or loving is essential to being a person.
“He can make whatever decision he likes and shape his will
as he pleases. This does not mean that his will is free. It only means that his
will is anarchic, moved by mere impulse and inclination. For a person without
ideals, there are no volitional laws he has bound himself to respect and to
which he unconditionally submits. He has no inviolable boundaries. Thus he is
amorphous with no fixed shape or identity.” (2)
If we accept the above then we should value loving firstly because
by loving we make ourselves into persons. Secondly what we love defines what
sort of persons we are. On a somewhat speculative note it might be suggested
children keep teddy for reasons of love. Teddy bears can’t love children so
perhaps children keep bears because of their need to love. I have also suggested
elsewhere that this need to love is one of the reasons some people keep pets,
see the philosopher's dog .
I have argued that it is more important to love than be loved.
Nonetheless to human beings and perhaps some other creatures such as dogs being
loved is also of major importance. To be loved means that a lover must care
about the interests of his loved one. Could someone be said to love another
person if he remained completely indifferent to the interests of that person?
It follows one reason we value being loved is because it advances our interests.
However our interests can be advanced by others acting from duty and doing so needn’t
involve love. Moreover even if most people want to be cared about they would nonetheless
regard simply being cared for as an incomplete form of love. Husbands, wives, romantic
partners, friends and children don’t want to be simply cared for in the way
someone cares about a pet, they want to be cared about because of the particular
people they are. It would appear that people want to be loved for a reason and
they want that reason to be based on the sort person they are, their
characteristics. Sven Nyholm expresses this want,
“Love is, in this way, a sort of confirmation that we are, as we might
put it, ‘lovable’ in the sense of being able to inspire or call forth such dispositions
in another (namely the lover).” (3)
A lover doesn’t love everyone but specific persons. What sort of specific qualities does a loved one need in order to create a disposition in his lover to love her? Prima Facie it might seem what creates such a disposition is the attributes the loved one possesses, for example someone might be loved because of her humour, tenacity and straight talking.
Unfortunately accepting the above raises three problems. First someone’s
loved one might be fungible. They can easily be replaced by someone else who
has the same attributes but to a greater degree or someone who has some
additional attributes. Using the above example above the loved one might be
replaced by someone who is funnier, has greater tenacity and whose conversation
is even more to the point. Or alternatively by someone who is just as funny, tenacious
and to the point but additionally is courageous. Nyholm seems to be suggesting
that someone want to be loveable because of certain attributes she possesses
but do we really love her or her attributes? If we love the attributes do we
really love the person at all? This echoes Platonic love with all its problems.
Of course it might be suggested that we
can’t separate a person from her attributes. A second problem arises if we love
someone for her attributes then we should also equally love someone else who
possesses identical attributes. Theoretically we could love a very large number
of people who possess these attributes. It might be argued that in practice we
don’t have the cognitive abilities to assess the attributes of a very large
number of people meaning that in practice we are only likely to love a subset of
the people who possess the same attributes. The number of people we can love
might also be limited by the Dunbar number. Nonetheless in practice we could
end up loving several people because they possess identical attributes. Of
course such a situation might be perfectly acceptable for the friends we go to
watch football with but does the same apply to romantic partners? Lastly do we
love our children because of their good qualities or simply because they are
our children? If we choose the first option then our love is conditional and I
would suggest that this would cause problems with childrearing.
Nonetheless in spite of the
above it is natural to see our children as possessing lovable qualities. However
more generally do we see these qualities as lovable prior to loving our loved
ones? If we don’t then perhaps we are labelling these qualities as lovable
partly in order to explain to ourselves why we love our loved ones. Our loved
ones don’t naturally possess lovable qualities we create them.
In the light of the above problems it might be suggested either that the
account of love I have outlined love above is an inadequate one and that it should
be replaced by a more adequate one or that there are different accounts of love
in different domains as proposed by Aristotle. I am reluctant to accept either
of these suggestions and will now give reasons for my reluctance. According to
Simon May love is an ancient emotion but that over the last hundred and fifty
years the dominant view of love has changed. Romantic love has been replaced by
love of our children, parental love (4). I have suggested above that far from
being a modern interpretation of what we mean by love that parental love forms
the basis of all other forms of love. Let us accept that parents caring about
their young offspring is a basic form of love. It is important to note caring
about isn’t equivalent to caring for, someone may care for another without
caring about him. Caring about means being vulnerable to the fate of the loved
one caring for doesn’t. I will now argue that this primitive form of love when
its domain is extended can account for our desire to be loved because of the specific
persons we are.
What are the reasons someone
has for loving us? It might be suggested that this question splits into two
further questions. First, what sort of reasons might someone have for coming to
love her loved one? Secondly what sort of reasons might have to continue loving
her loved one? It might be objected that the reasons are identical in both
situations. Accepting this objection means either that our original question
doesn’t really split into two as I have suggested or if it does the same
reasons satisfy both questions. Let us accept that the original question might
split into two. Someone might come to love her loved one because of his beauty
and years later continue loving him for another reason once this has faded. I
now want to argue that we need reasons to come to love someone but that once we
have done so we just continue loving her. We must have reason to come to love,
to bestow love, but that we don’t need reasons to continue loving. Once we come
to love someone we are simply satisfied with our love and we would need reasons
to come to stopping loving someone, becoming dissatisfied with our love. If we
accept the above then it is possible to explain why some people find it hard to
stop loving. For instance the mother of a paedophile might continue to love her
child in spite of the crimes he has committed. She came to love him because he
was her child and once her love was established she became satisfied with her
love.
What reasons do we have to
come to love someone? I would suggest one sort of reason is the relationship
between the lover and the loved one. A parent comes to love her child because
he is her child, a friend loves her friend because he is her friend and
romantic partners love each other because they are romantic partners. The fact
that parents love their own children rather than other children who are just as
cute, intelligent and charming seems to support the above. This suggestion is
based on Niko Kolodmy’s idea of love as a valuing relationship (5). These
reasons define the domain of love rather than love itself. It might be objected
that some prior relationship isn’t a necessary condition for coming to love a
loved one, one simply does it. Accepting the above raises the possibility of
love at first sight. It might be argued that the type of love I have outlined
above is unable to explain love at first sight. In response to this objection
it might be argued that love at first sight is illusory. However even if we
accept that love at first sight exists it can be explained by the type of love
outlined above. I have argued above that we have a need both to be loved and to
love. I argued above that we have a greater need to love than be loved. It
follows that the reason for love at first sight can be satisfied by our need to
love.
I have suggested that love was originally a simple emotion which has changed as we have evolved. It has been changed by our empathy, increased cognitive powers and we fact we live in a particular culture. I would now suggest that these changes have altered what we love, expanded the domain of our love, but haven’t changed how we love. I have also suggested that whilst we have reasons why we come to love someone we don’t have any reason to continue loving. Relationships give us reason to love someone but our love simply persists because we are satisfied with our love. If we accept the above what does this mean for Nyholm’s contention that we have a desire to be lovable. It certainly means we can’t be considered lovable because of some of the attributes we possess. But do we really want to be loved for our attributes? If we are wise and loved for our wisdom we would still want to be loved if we lost our wisdom. If we are loved for our caring we would still want to be loved when we become old have to be cared for rather than care for others. Perhaps we simply want to be loved rather than loved for some of our attributes. We simply want to be loved rather than loved for a reason. Accepting the above means there are reasons why we come to be loved but no reasons our continuing to be loved. We come to be loved because of we are the children of someone, the parent of a child or simply a friend. Accepting the above also helps explain why the parents of severely handicapped child love and regard him as irreplaceable even if he possesses few lovable properties. Perhaps we should be grateful for being loved and the benefits it brings.
- Barrett, Lisa Feldman, 2017, How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain, Pan Macmillan, page 30
- Harry Frankfurt, 1999 Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge University Press. Page 114
- Sven Nyholm,‘Love troubles: Human attachment and biomedical enhancements’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 32, 2 (2015): 190–2
- Simon May,2019, Love, a New Understanding of an Ancient Emotion, Oxford University Press, page 21[js1]
- Niko Kolodny, 2003, Love as Valuing a Relationship, The Philosophical
Review, Vol. 112(2).
Engaging with Robots
In an interesting paper Sven Nyholm considers some of the implications of controlling robots. I use the idea of control to ask a different...
-
In his posting on practical ethics Shlomit Harrosh connects the rights of death row inmates in certain states of the USA to choose the met...
-
According to Max Wind-Cowie shame should be liberated rather than legislated for. By this I take Wind-Cowie to mean that shame should pl...
-
Kristjan Kristjansson argues too much attention is paid to promoting an individual’s self esteem and not enough to promoting his self res...