- Tim Dunlop, Why the future is workless, (Kindle Locations 1748-1749). New South. Kindle Edition.
- Harry Frankfurt, 2006, The Reasons of Love, Princetown, University Press, page 54
- Samuel Clark, 2017, Good Work, Journal of Applied Philosophy 34(1), Page 66.
- Clark, page 66.
- Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge University Press. Page 135.
This blog is concerned with most topics in applied philosophy. In particular it is concerned with autonomy, love and other emotions. comments are most welcome
Tuesday, 14 March 2017
Automation, Work and Education
Wednesday, 22 February 2017
Sex with Robots
In the near future it seems probable that some people will
have sex with robots, see the rise of the love
droids . In this posting I will discuss some of the problems this possibility
raises. I will divide my discussion into two parts. For the most part my
discussion will consider sex with robots which are simply machines before
moving on, and much more fancifully, to discussing sex with robots which might
be considered as persons.
Let us consider someone having sex with a robot which isn’t
a person, is simply a machine. Human beings have created objects to be used for
sexual purposes such as vibrators and other sex toys. If a robot isn’t a person,
then it might appear that someone having sex with a robot is unproblematic in
much the same way as is the use of these artefacts. I now want to argue that
this appearance is false. But before making my argument I want to consider the
nature of sex. Sex among humans isn’t simply a matter of reproduction. Human
beings enjoy sex. Neither is this enjoyment a purely mechanical thing.
According to Robert Nozick,
“Sex is not simply a matter of frictional force. The
excitement comes largely in how we interpret the situation and how we perceive
the connection to the other. Even in masturbatory fantasy, people dwell upon
their actions with others; they do not get excited by thinking of themselves
whilst masturbating. “(1)
If we accept that Nozick’s view what does having sex with a
robot really mean to the person having sex? Provided a robot has been supplied with
the appropriate genitalia would someone might want to have sex with it? I would
suggest it does not in many cases. Let us assume that a robot has the
appropriate genitalia, four legs, one arm and several detachable eyes. I would
suggest very few people would want to have sex with such a machine. Nozick
argues even when masturbating someone is imaging having sex with another person
and I would suggest much the same applies to having sex with a robot. If
someone has sex with a robot, he would want it to look like a beautiful person
because he is imagining having sex with such a person.
What are the implications of accepting the importance of such
imagining? First I would suggest having sex with a robot is just an enhanced
form of masturbation. Masturbation isn’t wrong because it doesn’t harm others.
Having sex with any robot which is purely a machine doesn’t harm others and so
by analogy also isn’t wrong. Indeed, in some circumstances masturbation might
be an acceptable choice for those who are physically or emotionally
incapacitated and perhaps also for those who are incarcerated. However even if
we accept the above masturbation isn’t ideal and neither would be sex with a
robot. Someone having imaginary sex with a person is having inferior sex
because what he desires is real sex.
I have argued that the first reason why someone might want
to have sex with a robot is that he cannot have sex with another person and
that there is nothing wrong with his actions. Anyone having sex with a robot
knows he cannot harm the robot. This gives rise to a second reason why someone
might want to have sex with a robot. Someone might know that the type of sexual
activity he wants to indulge in might be harmful to another human being and
because he knows he cannot harm a robot he prefers to indulge in this activity
with a robot. Does acting on such a preference matter for after all he isn’t
harming anyone else? Kant argued we shouldn’t be cruel to animals as this might
make us cruel to human beings. Might it be then if someone engages in such sexual
activity with a robot that this activity might make him more likely to engage
in harmful sexual acts with other human beings? At present there is no conclusive evidence to
support Kant’s argument that if someone is cruel to animals that this cruelty
makes him more likely to be cruel to other people. If this is so it seems
doubtful that if someone engages in such sexual activity with a robot that his activity
would not make him more likely to do so with another human being. The above is
an empirical question and cannot be settled by philosophical analysis. However,
someone engaging in sex with a robot, which would be harmful to a human being
might harm himself. I have previously argued that for the users of pornography
there is a split between fantasy and reality, see wooler.scottus
. I further argued in the case of sexual practices which might harm others that
the maintenance of the split between fantasy and reality is absolutely
essential. I have argued above that someone having sex with a robot imagines he
is having sex with a person. It follows for someone engaging in sex with a
robot, which might harm another human being, that the maintenance of the split
between fantasy and reality is also essential. I further argued that if someone
uses pornography that this split threatens the unity of his will which is
damaging to his identity. It follows that someone engaging in sex with a robot,
which would be harmful to a human being might harm himself by damaging his
identity.
Some people assume at some time in the future some robots
might become persons. I am extremely sceptical about this possibility but
nonetheless I will now consider some of the problems of someone having sex with
such a robot. However, before I do so I will question whether anyone would want
sex with such a robot. Let us accept Nozick is correct in his assertion that
“sex is not simply a matter of frictional force. The excitement comes largely
in how we interpret the situation and how we perceive the connection to the
other.” How do we perceive the connection to a robot which is also a person? I
suggested above that a robot can take many forms. Would anyone want to have sex
with a robot with four legs, one arm, several detachable eyes, appropriate
genitalia even if it could be considered as a person? Persons are partly
defined by the actions they are capable of enacting and these actions are
partly defined by their bodies’ capabilities. Robots can have very different
bodies from us. A robot with a different body structure might be capable of
very different actions to us, such a robot even if it is considered as a person
might be very different sort of person to the sort we are. The same might also
be true of a robot with similar structure which is constructed from different
materials. If someone or something is very different to us then the connection
between us and that someone or something becomes tenuous. Would someone want to
sex with any robot with which he had only a tenuous connection, I doubt it. Of
course someone might want to have sex with such a robot provided it looked like
a beautiful human being. But if this is so isn’t he really imaging having sex
with a person and the problems associated with having sex with a robot which is
purely a machine once again become relevant.
In conclusion I have argued that someone would not harm others by having sex with a robot and his actions would not be morally wrong. However, I argued whilst it might not be wrong to have sex with any robot which is purely a machine that it might nonetheless be damaging to the user’s identity, in much the same way as pornography, by splitting character. Lastly questioned whether anyone would really want to have sex with any robot which might be considered as a person.
- 1. Robert Nozick, 1989, The Examined Life, Touchstone, page 61
Monday, 23 January 2017
Robots and Persons
- Immanuel Kant, 1785, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,
- Harry Frankfurt, 1988, The Importance of What We Care about, Cambridge University Press, page 83.
Monday, 21 November 2016
Cryonic Preservation and Physician Assisted Suicide
- Type 1 CP will be defined as the preservation by freezing of a dead body in the hope that a cure for the disease that body died from becomes available in the future in the hope that he may be resuscitated and cured.
- Type 2 CP will be defined as the preservation by freezing of someone’s body whilst he is alive in the hope that a cure for the disease he suffers from becomes available in the future in the hope that he may be resuscitated and cured.
Tuesday, 8 November 2016
Nussbaum, Transitional Anger and Unconditional Forgiveness
2. Martha Nussbaum, 2016, Anger and Forgiveness, Oxford University Press, Chapter 3.
3. Nussbaum, chapter 3.
5. List of Griswold’s conditions as outlined by Nussbaum.
· Acknowledge she was the responsible agent.
· Repudiate her deed (by acknowledging it. Express regret to the injured at having caused this particular injury to her
· Commit to becoming a better short of person who does not commit injury and show this commitment through deeds as well as words.
· Show how she understands from the injured person’s perspective the damage done by the injury. Offer a narrative of accounting for how she came to do the wrong, how the wrongdoing does not express the totality of the person and how she became worthy of approbation.
· Acknowledge she was the responsible agent. Repudiate her deed (by acknowledging its wrongness) and herself as the cause.
· Express regret to the injured at having caused this particular injury to her.
· Commit to becoming a better short of person who does not commit injury and show this commitment through deeds as well as words.
· Show how she understands from the injured person’s perspective the damage done by the injury. Offer a narrative of accounting for how she came to do the wrong, how the wrongdoing does not express the totality of the person and how she became worthy of approbation.
6. MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, 2015, Transitional Anger. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, page 51.
7. Michael S. Brady, 2013, Emotional Insight; The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience, Oxford University Press
8. MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, 2015, Transitional Anger. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, page 54.
Friday, 28 October 2016
Montgomery and the Information needed for Valid Informed Consent
- Steve Clarke, 2001, Informed Consent in Medicine in Comparison with Consent with Consent in Other Areas of Human Activity, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39, page 177
Tuesday, 4 October 2016
A Duty to permit Assisted Suicide?
In previous postings I have argued that we should accept that terminally ill people have a right to die and that we should respect that right by accepting assisted suicide. My arguments were based on respecting autonomy and of course respecting autonomy involves duties. However in this posting I want to focus more directly on duties. I will argue that we have a duty not to cause terminally ill people who are suffering to continue to existing against their will. We have a duty not to force innocent people endure pain in order to protect the vulnerable, surely the vulnerable can be protected in better ways.My argument will be based on the premise that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being which would find its life not worth living.
Let us accept the above premise without argument. I now want to suggest that the duty not to bring into existence any being we think would not find its life worth living is analogous to a proposed duty not to cause any being to continue to exist against its will if its life is not living. Accepting this analogy would have implications for using animals in medical research but in the following discussion I will limit my argument to assisted suicide. It might be objected that my suggested analogy fails for two reasons. First, it might we objected that by refusing to grant the right to assisted suicide to these people we do not cause them to lead lives which are not worth living. Secondly it might be objected even if some people do experience lives which are not worth living this would be better rectified by changing the conditions of these lives rather than by making assisted suicide available to such people. I will deal with each of these objections in turn.
Let us accept that that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being we think would find its life not worth living. We have a duty not to cause the existence of such lives. My objector might accept this premise. We shouldn’t enslave or torture people for instance. But he might argue that we don’t cause terminally ill patients or prisoners serving life sentences to lead lives not worth living and as a result my analogy fails. The cause of their misfortune is due to disease or past crimes. He might then proceed further by suggesting even if we are a partial cause of the type of lives some people live that a partial cause doesn’t give rise to a duty. Let accept that my objector does accept that he has duty not cause a child to come into existence who wouldn’t have a life worth living. Let us assume this child wouldn’t have a life worth living due to some genetic defect. It follows anyone who permits such a child come into existence is only a partial cause of the child not having a life worth living. It would appear my objector must accept either that our partial causation of some event can incur duties or that there is nothing wrong with causing a child to exist when he will not have a life worth living due to genetic defects. In the light of the above example my initial premise might be amended as follows. We have a duty not to be the partial cause of the existence of any being which wouldn’t have a life worth living. If someone accepts my amended premise, then it might be argued by analogy that we also have a duty not to be the partial cause of someone continuing to live a life he doesn’t find worth living.
At this point my objector might raise a second objection to my analogy. He might point out that in my amended premise we only have a binary option of causing or not causing existence. He might proceed to further point out that for both those suffering from terminal illnesses and prisoners serving life sentences other options are available. For terminally ill patients we could improve palliative care and for prisoners serving life sentences we might improve penal conditions. I accept my objectors point and accept that provided other options are available which would allow both of these categories of people to live lives they would find worth living my analogy fails. I also accept that improvements in palliative care and prison conditions are desirable and should be carried out. However, I do not accept that such improvements always means we are not the cause of making someone live a live he finds not worth living. Simply removing pain from a terminally patient’s life doesn’t mean he has a life worth living. We can remove all pain from someone by putting him in an induced coma for the rest of his life. Would such a patient really be alive? I would argue if someone is unconscious and will never regain consciousness he is in a state equivalent to being dead, he is certainly not living any sort of live at all. Whether it is possible to remove almost all the pain from all conscious terminally ill patients so that pain by itself doesn’t mean they don’t have lives worth living is an empirical question. Personally I doubt whether this will be possible in all cases but I will not pursue the point here. However, even if we could reduce pain to acceptable levels for all terminally ill patients it does not follow that they have lives which they believe are worth living. A life worth living is not just a question of having a relatively pain free conscious existence. Is simply existing really living? A very limited lifespan together with vastly impaired capabilities might well mean some such people find their lives lacking all meaning, find their lives not worth living. I would suggest anyone who suggests otherwise might be accused of epistemic arrogance. It follows even if palliative care was much improved there would still be some terminally ill patients living lives which they would find to be not worth living. It might also be argued much improved prison conditions don’t automatically mean prisoners serving life sentences always find their lives worth living. Some such prisoners might suffer from remorse which makes their lives not worth living. Indeed, better penal conditions might increase such prisoners’ propensity to suffer remorse. Other such prisoners might find the impossibility of freedom makes their lives meaningless, not worth living. It again follows that improved penal conditions would not mean all prisoners serving life sentences would have lives they considered to be worth living.
In the light of the above it appears, if we accept the premise that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being which would find its life not worth living that we also have a duty not to cause people to continue to exist if they have lives not worth living. It follows we should permit assisted suicide to those suffering from terminal illness. Accepting the above might also mean some patients with a terminal diagnosis who find their lives worth living might better enjoy their lives if they had the reassurance that if these lives became unbearable they could be helped to end them removing their worries about how these lives might end.
Engaging with Robots
In an interesting paper Sven Nyholm considers some of the implications of controlling robots. I use the idea of control to ask a different...
-
In his posting on practical ethics Shlomit Harrosh connects the rights of death row inmates in certain states of the USA to choose the met...
-
According to Max Wind-Cowie shame should be liberated rather than legislated for. By this I take Wind-Cowie to mean that shame should pl...
-
Kristjan Kristjansson argues too much attention is paid to promoting an individual’s self esteem and not enough to promoting his self res...