In this posting I want to consider Mark Alfano’s idea of
factitous virtue, I will only consider factitious moral virtue (1). In recent
years the whole idea that human beings can possess virtues has come under
sustained attack from moral psychologists and many would now question whether
virtue ethics has any real future. Moral psychologists argue that all that
really matters when we make moral decisions are the situations we find
ourselves in and not any supposed virtues we might possess. However, if all that
matters are the situations people find themselves in when making such decisions
then everyone should act in a similar fashion in a similar situation. Clearly this
isn’t true. People’s character varies. It is conceivable that someone’s character
is partly shaped by her moral behaviour, being a trusty person is part of that
person’s character. Perhaps virtue is hard and limited to a few people or
perhaps most people only have limited virtue. In this posting I will argue that
if virtue matters that it does so in two specific domains. I will then consider
whether Alfano’s factitious virtue can be considered a virtue in the
traditional sense. Lastly I will consider whether factitious virtue matters.
Let us consider the way we make moral decisions. When
making important moral decisions with wide scale implications virtue ethics is
not really useful. Some might disagree with the above. When making important
moral decisions we don’t simply do what a virtuous person would do, we think.
We think of the consequences or perhaps we question whether any decision we
make could be made into a universal law. When making important decisions, such
as those concerning the consequences of global warming or whether terminally
ill patients should have the right to assisted suicide, then thinking about
consequences or universal laws seem to be better way forward than simply asking
what a virtuous person would do. I will not consider whether we should employ
consequentialist or deontological methods here. It might be thought in the
light of the above that I believe virtue should play no part in moral decision
making. Such a thought would be premature. Not all moral decisions are of wide
scale importance, for instance a daughter might have to decide whether to help
her aged mother to go shopping or spend an enjoyable afternoon by herself in
her garden on a beautiful summer’s day. Such decisions are not made after
careful consideration but rather by simply deciding, deciding in accordance
with our virtues, provided of course this is possible. It follows there is a possible
place for the virtues in making some moral decisions, Bernard Williams would
have classed such decisions as ethical decisions, see Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy . Virtue
would be useful in the domain of making every-day moral or ethical decisions
provided virtue is possible. I now want to argue that virtue might also matter
in a second domain. Alfano suggests that,
“People enjoy acting in accordance with their own
self-concepts, even those aspects of self-concept that are evaluatively
neutral; they’re averse to acting contrary to their self-concepts, especially
the evaluatively positive aspects of their self-concepts.” (2)
I’m not sure Alfano is totally correct when he suggests
people enjoy acting in accordance
with their self-concepts. I would suggest people are satisfied with acting in accordance with their self-concept and hence
have no reason to act otherwise. I would however agree with Alfano that people
do act in accordance with their self-concepts. The daughter in in example I
used above makes her decision based on her self-concept. She might consider
herself to be a caring person and as a result takes her mother shopping. It
follows that if we partly define ourselves by the virtues we possess that
virtue matters in the domain of self-definition.
Let us accept that there is a possible domain for virtue in
moral decision making. I would suggest that this is not a trivial domain
because most of the moral decisions we make are everyday ones and our concept
of self matters. I would further suggest that we have evolved a capacity to
make every day moral decisions and find it hard to transcend this capacity.
However, even if there is a possible domain for the virtues in making moral
decision this possibility by itself doesn’t mean the virtues exist. A lot of psychological
research seems to point to the situation someone finds herself in when making
moral decisions being much more important than any supposed virtue she might
possess. In 1972 Alice Isen and Paula Levin conducted a famous experiment which
showed participants who found a dime in a payphone were much more likely to aid
someone needing help (3). Many other studies have replicated Isen and Levin’s
finding that what really matters when making a moral decision is the context
the decision is made in rather than any supposed virtue the decision maker
possesses. Let us accept for the sake of argument that virtue is weak or rare
in most people and hence not a useful concept as far as most people are
concerned.
In the light of the situationist challenge Alfano argues
that the idea of factitious virtue is useful. What exactly is factitious
virtue? Alfano suggests that factitious virtue is a kind of self-fulfilling
prophecy. He gives us an example of a self-fulfilling prophecy.
“Were United States Federal Reserve Chairman Ben Bernanke
to announce …. On a Sunday evening that the stock market would collapse the
next day, people would react by selling their portfilios, leading indeed to a
stock market crash. (4)
A factitious virtue is analogous to a self-fulfilling
prophecy. Alfano argues if you label someone as having a virtue that she comes
to act as if she possesses the virtue, she has factitious virtue.
“Virtue labelling causes factitious virtue, in which people
behave in accordance with virtue not because they possess the trait in question
but because that trait has been attributed to them.” (5)
For labelling to be effective it should be made in public
and believable to the person labelled. Let us return to my previous example.
Telling the daughter in my example that she is a caring person when she has
just parked in a disabled bay would not be a case of virtue labelling. Telling the
daughter in public that she is a caring person when she has just helped someone
to cross the road would be a case of virtue labelling and would mean that she
would be more likely to help her mother with her shopping.
Let us examine the status of a factitious virtue. The
question then naturally arises is factitious virtue a real virtue? Alfano uses
an analogy between a placebo and factious virtue to explain how factitious
virtue works. If someone believes that a placebo will help her then her belief
is a self-fulfilling one. In the same way someone believes she has a virtue due
to labelling then she has factitious virtue. But a placebo isn’t a drug and it
might be argued by analogy that factitious virtue is a not real virtue. What do
we mean by a virtue? According to the Cambridge Online Dictionary virtue is “a
good moral quality in a person or the general quality of being morally good.”
If we accept the above definition then factitious virtue is a real virtue in a
narrow sense because it induces a good quality in a person and the argument by
analogy fails, however labelling does not seem to induce the more global
quality of someone being morally good.
I now want to examine whether factitious virtue is a real
virtue in the broader sense of being connected to being a morally good person.
Factitious virtue differs from the more traditional virtues in the way it is
acquired, does this difference in acquisition mean factitious virtue is not a
real virtue? Julia Annas argues we acquire the virtues by learning (6). Learning
requires some skill. If someone acquires a factitious virtue of caring by means
of labelling then her acquisition need not involve any skill. It follows,
provided Annas is correct, that factitious virtue is not a real virtue. Annas
further argues we cannot acquire a moral virtue in isolation, for instance
someone cannot learn to be caring without also learning to be just. Perhaps we
can acquire non-moral virtues such as courage in isolation. It follows if someone
acquires one moral virtue that in doing so she must acquire others because
there is some unity of the moral virtues and this leads her to being a morally
good person. Beneficence is a moral virtue and someone might become more beneficent
by being labelled as caring. Acquiring the factitious virtue of caring by
labelling doesn’t require that someone acquires any other moral virtues. It
again follows provided Annas is correct that factitious virtue is not a real
virtue in the broader sense. However factitious virtue remains a real virtue in
the narrow sense because it induces a good quality in a person.
I now want to consider two objections to regarding
factitious virtue as a real virtue in even the narrow sense. Firstly, it might
be argued that any real virtue must be stable over time and that once labelling
ceases a factitious virtue slowly decays over time. Michael Bishop argues that
positive causal networks PCN are self-sustaining (7). A PCN is a cluster of
mental states which sustain each other in a cyclical way. For instance,
confidence and optimism might aid some to be more successful and her success in
turn boosts her confidence and optimism. Bishop argues that successful
relationships, positive affect and healthy relationships skills/patterns form
such a network (8). Healthy relationship skills include trusting, being
responsive to someone’s needs and offering support. Healthy relationship skills
involve caring and so it is possible that caring is part of a self-sustaining
network. It follows it is possible that if the factitious virtue of caring is
induced in someone that once induced this factious virtue has some stability.
Whether such a possibility exists for other factitious virtues is not a
question for philosophy but for empirical research. It would appear that at
least one important factitious virtue, the one of caring, might be stable over
time and that this might be true of others.
Secondly it might be argued that a virtue is not something
we simply accept, not something induced in us in the same way a virus might
induce a disease. It might be argued that unless we autonomously accept some
virtue, it isn’t a real virtue. I accept this argument. It might then be
further argued that because we don’t autonomously accept a factitious virtue
that factitious virtues aren’t really virtues. I would reject this further
argument. There is a difference between autonomously accepting something and
making an autonomous decision. What does it mean to autonomously accept
something? I would suggest it means identifying oneself with the thing one
accepts. It means caring about something. This caring about means someone “makes
himself vulnerable to losses and susceptible to benefits depending upon whether
what he cares about is diminished or enhanced” according to Frankfurt (9). It
might be suggested if a factitious virtue is induced in us that there is no
need for us to identify with that virtue. I now want to argue that the above
suggestion is unsound. According to Frankfurt what someone loves, ‘cares about’
or identifies with is defined by her motivational structures.
“That a person cares about
something or that he loves something has less to do with how things make him
feel, or his opinions about them, than the more or less stable motivational
structures that shape his preferences and guide his conduct (10).
Frankfurt also believes our
motivational structures are defined by what we are satisfied with, passively
accept (11). To autonomously accept something means we are satisfied with our acceptance
and experience no resistance to or restlessness with that acceptance. Let us
return to factitious virtue. Labelling if it is to be effective must be done in
the right circumstances. Labelling
must be public and believable to the person labelled. In my previous example telling
the daughter in question that she is a caring person when she has just parked
in a disabled bay would not be a case of virtue labelling. Telling the daughter
in public that she is a caring person when she has just helped someone to cross
the road would be a case of virtue labelling and she would be unlikely to
resist such labelling. If we accept the above analysis of autonomous acceptance
then the daughter autonomously accepts the factitious virtue. I would also
suggest that a lack resistance or restlessness to accepting what children are
being taught is the way in which traditional virtue ethicists see them as
coming to autonomously accept the virtues they are being taught. It follows
that we autonomously accept factitious virtues in much the same way we accept
real virtues.
Does factitious virtue
matter? Let us accept without argument that the world would be a better place
if people acted virtuously. Let us also accept that factitious virtues act in much
the same way as real virtues at least for a period. It follows factitious
virtues can make the world a better place for a period even if these virtues
are relatively short lived. It would also appear that because the factitious
virtue of caring has some stability it can have improve the world in a more
lasting way. Intuitively a more caring world is a better world. However, it
might be argued that our intuitions are unsound. Factitious virtue might indeed
make people more caring but only by caring more for those already close to them
to the detriment of others. In response to the above argument firstly I would point
out not all ethical decisions are best made by considering what a virtuous
person would do. Some ethical decisions are best made using consequentialist or
deontological considerations. Secondly it might be feasible to extend the
domain of factitious caring by well-considered labelling. Labelling someone as
caring for strangers in the right circumstances might extend this domain.
Accepting the above means accepting that the factitious virtue of caring might well
improve the world in a more lasting way and that the factitious virtue of
caring matters.
- Mark Alfano, 2013, Character as Moral Fiction, Cambridge University Press.
- Alfano, 4.1
- Alice Isen & Paula Levin, 1972, The effect of feeling good on helping; cookies and kindness, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 34, 385-83.
- Alfano, 4.2.2
- Alfano, 4.3.1
- Julia Annas, 2011, Intelligent Virtue, Oxford University Press, page 84.
- Michael Bishop. 2015, The Good Life, Oxford University Press, Chp 3.
- Bishop, page 75.
- Harry Frankfurt, 1988, The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University Press, page 83.
- Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge University Press. Page 129
- Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love, page 103.
1 comment:
"When making important moral decisions with wide scale implications virtue ethics is not really useful." (sorry for my bad english, i'm french-speaking) Very interesting paper. But what about practical wisdom (phronesis) and other intellectual virtues ? It seems to me that we would use intellectual virtues in these "decisions with wide scale implications". A virtuous agent is not only a good person at a moral level, but also a clever, smart and wise person. Considering global warming, what would do a virtuous agent (that means also a wise or reasonable agent) ? He will consider the probable consequences of the different possible political decisions and he will choose what it seems to be the best for the future of his family, his descendants, his tribe and his planet. He will then first think to preserve their life and not their change purse.
Post a Comment