- Type 1 CP will be defined as the preservation by freezing of a dead body in the hope that a cure for the disease that body died from becomes available in the future in the hope that he may be resuscitated and cured.
- Type 2 CP will be defined as the preservation by freezing of someone’s body whilst he is alive in the hope that a cure for the disease he suffers from becomes available in the future in the hope that he may be resuscitated and cured.
This blog is concerned with most topics in applied philosophy. In particular it is concerned with autonomy, love and other emotions. comments are most welcome
Monday, 21 November 2016
Cryonic Preservation and Physician Assisted Suicide
Tuesday, 8 November 2016
Nussbaum, Transitional Anger and Unconditional Forgiveness
2. Martha Nussbaum, 2016, Anger and Forgiveness, Oxford University Press, Chapter 3.
3. Nussbaum, chapter 3.
5. List of Griswold’s conditions as outlined by Nussbaum.
· Acknowledge she was the responsible agent.
· Repudiate her deed (by acknowledging it. Express regret to the injured at having caused this particular injury to her
· Commit to becoming a better short of person who does not commit injury and show this commitment through deeds as well as words.
· Show how she understands from the injured person’s perspective the damage done by the injury. Offer a narrative of accounting for how she came to do the wrong, how the wrongdoing does not express the totality of the person and how she became worthy of approbation.
· Acknowledge she was the responsible agent. Repudiate her deed (by acknowledging its wrongness) and herself as the cause.
· Express regret to the injured at having caused this particular injury to her.
· Commit to becoming a better short of person who does not commit injury and show this commitment through deeds as well as words.
· Show how she understands from the injured person’s perspective the damage done by the injury. Offer a narrative of accounting for how she came to do the wrong, how the wrongdoing does not express the totality of the person and how she became worthy of approbation.
6. MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, 2015, Transitional Anger. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, page 51.
7. Michael S. Brady, 2013, Emotional Insight; The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience, Oxford University Press
8. MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, 2015, Transitional Anger. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, page 54.
Friday, 28 October 2016
Montgomery and the Information needed for Valid Informed Consent
- Steve Clarke, 2001, Informed Consent in Medicine in Comparison with Consent with Consent in Other Areas of Human Activity, The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39, page 177
Tuesday, 4 October 2016
A Duty to permit Assisted Suicide?
In previous postings I have argued that we should accept that terminally ill people have a right to die and that we should respect that right by accepting assisted suicide. My arguments were based on respecting autonomy and of course respecting autonomy involves duties. However in this posting I want to focus more directly on duties. I will argue that we have a duty not to cause terminally ill people who are suffering to continue to existing against their will. We have a duty not to force innocent people endure pain in order to protect the vulnerable, surely the vulnerable can be protected in better ways.My argument will be based on the premise that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being which would find its life not worth living.
Let us accept the above premise without argument. I now want to suggest that the duty not to bring into existence any being we think would not find its life worth living is analogous to a proposed duty not to cause any being to continue to exist against its will if its life is not living. Accepting this analogy would have implications for using animals in medical research but in the following discussion I will limit my argument to assisted suicide. It might be objected that my suggested analogy fails for two reasons. First, it might we objected that by refusing to grant the right to assisted suicide to these people we do not cause them to lead lives which are not worth living. Secondly it might be objected even if some people do experience lives which are not worth living this would be better rectified by changing the conditions of these lives rather than by making assisted suicide available to such people. I will deal with each of these objections in turn.
Let us accept that that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being we think would find its life not worth living. We have a duty not to cause the existence of such lives. My objector might accept this premise. We shouldn’t enslave or torture people for instance. But he might argue that we don’t cause terminally ill patients or prisoners serving life sentences to lead lives not worth living and as a result my analogy fails. The cause of their misfortune is due to disease or past crimes. He might then proceed further by suggesting even if we are a partial cause of the type of lives some people live that a partial cause doesn’t give rise to a duty. Let accept that my objector does accept that he has duty not cause a child to come into existence who wouldn’t have a life worth living. Let us assume this child wouldn’t have a life worth living due to some genetic defect. It follows anyone who permits such a child come into existence is only a partial cause of the child not having a life worth living. It would appear my objector must accept either that our partial causation of some event can incur duties or that there is nothing wrong with causing a child to exist when he will not have a life worth living due to genetic defects. In the light of the above example my initial premise might be amended as follows. We have a duty not to be the partial cause of the existence of any being which wouldn’t have a life worth living. If someone accepts my amended premise, then it might be argued by analogy that we also have a duty not to be the partial cause of someone continuing to live a life he doesn’t find worth living.
At this point my objector might raise a second objection to my analogy. He might point out that in my amended premise we only have a binary option of causing or not causing existence. He might proceed to further point out that for both those suffering from terminal illnesses and prisoners serving life sentences other options are available. For terminally ill patients we could improve palliative care and for prisoners serving life sentences we might improve penal conditions. I accept my objectors point and accept that provided other options are available which would allow both of these categories of people to live lives they would find worth living my analogy fails. I also accept that improvements in palliative care and prison conditions are desirable and should be carried out. However, I do not accept that such improvements always means we are not the cause of making someone live a live he finds not worth living. Simply removing pain from a terminally patient’s life doesn’t mean he has a life worth living. We can remove all pain from someone by putting him in an induced coma for the rest of his life. Would such a patient really be alive? I would argue if someone is unconscious and will never regain consciousness he is in a state equivalent to being dead, he is certainly not living any sort of live at all. Whether it is possible to remove almost all the pain from all conscious terminally ill patients so that pain by itself doesn’t mean they don’t have lives worth living is an empirical question. Personally I doubt whether this will be possible in all cases but I will not pursue the point here. However, even if we could reduce pain to acceptable levels for all terminally ill patients it does not follow that they have lives which they believe are worth living. A life worth living is not just a question of having a relatively pain free conscious existence. Is simply existing really living? A very limited lifespan together with vastly impaired capabilities might well mean some such people find their lives lacking all meaning, find their lives not worth living. I would suggest anyone who suggests otherwise might be accused of epistemic arrogance. It follows even if palliative care was much improved there would still be some terminally ill patients living lives which they would find to be not worth living. It might also be argued much improved prison conditions don’t automatically mean prisoners serving life sentences always find their lives worth living. Some such prisoners might suffer from remorse which makes their lives not worth living. Indeed, better penal conditions might increase such prisoners’ propensity to suffer remorse. Other such prisoners might find the impossibility of freedom makes their lives meaningless, not worth living. It again follows that improved penal conditions would not mean all prisoners serving life sentences would have lives they considered to be worth living.
In the light of the above it appears, if we accept the premise that we have a duty not to bring into existence any being which would find its life not worth living that we also have a duty not to cause people to continue to exist if they have lives not worth living. It follows we should permit assisted suicide to those suffering from terminal illness. Accepting the above might also mean some patients with a terminal diagnosis who find their lives worth living might better enjoy their lives if they had the reassurance that if these lives became unbearable they could be helped to end them removing their worries about how these lives might end.
Wednesday, 14 September 2016
Happiness and Consumerism
- Fred Feldman, 2010, What is this thing called Happiness? Oxford, page 29.
- Daniel Haybron, 2008, The Pursuit of Unhappiness, Oxford, page 147.
- Haybron, page 138.
- Haybron, page 113
- Martin Seligman, 2011, Flourish, Nicholas Brealey Publishing, Chapter 1.
- Haybron, page 130.
Tuesday, 16 August 2016
Sport, Motivational Enhancement and Authenticity
Heather Dyke writing in the conversation examines why
doping in sport is wrong. In a previous posting I have argued that doping in
sport is wrong for three main reasons, see sport performance and enhancing drugs
. Firstly, I believe there should be a difference between sport and simple
spectacle and that the use performance enhancing drugs by sportspersons erodes
this difference. Secondly I argued that permitting performance enhancing drugs
simply moves the goalposts. If we don’t permit the use of all drugs, including
dangerous ones, we will still have to test whether any drugs used are permitted
ones. Lastly I argued what we admire about sport is linked to the determination
and effort required by sportspersons and that the use of performance enhancing
drugs weakens this link. Determination and effort are linked to motivation, to
character. I have previously argued that it would not be wrong to enhance our
motivation, see effectiveness enhancement . It
would appear that I hold two conflicting positions with regard to doping in
sport. In this posting I want to examine this conflict.
Let me start my examination by making it clear the sort of
doping I am opposed to. I believe any drug which enhances an athlete’s body
damages sport for the three reasons outlined above. If some mediocre athlete
could transform himself into an Olympic champion in a matter of weeks by taking
some drug which vastly physically enhanced him would we really admire him? I
would suggest we would not because we feel sporting excellence should require
some effort. Now let us consider a second mediocre athlete who transforms
himself into an Olympic champion over by taking some drug which enhances his
motivation over a number of years. By transforming his motivation, he trains
more determinedly and makes greater effort when training. This second athlete
raises three interesting questions. Firstly, is there any real difference in a
sporting context between an athlete taking a drug to enhance himself physically
and enhance himself mentally? Secondly would we admire such an athlete? Lastly
is the enhancement of someone’s motivation compatible with the ethos of sport?
I will now attempt to answer each of the above a questions
in turn. Is there any real difference in a sporting context between an athlete
taking a drug to enhance himself physically and enhance himself mentally?
Clearly there is a difference in this case because an athlete who enhances
himself physically with the use of drugs need make no effort to achieve his
enhancement whilst a second athlete who physically enhances herself by mentally
enhancing her motivation must still train hard. Does this difference matter?
The answer this additional question is connected to our second original
question. What do we admire about sportspeople? I would suggest we admire their
dedication to the effort required for their sport, we admire their motivation
for sport, we admire part of their character. Of course it follows we need not
admire all of a sportsperson’s character. Let us accept that we admire a
sportsperson’s motivation, effort and dedication. The question now would admire
his motivation, effort and dedication if these were artificially enhanced?
It might be argued that if we obtain certain goods easily
without any real determination that in so doing we devalue determination in
general. Let us assume it is possible to artificially enhance our motivation by
making us more determined. Let us accept that if an athlete enhances himself
physically by the use of drugs, gene therapy or blood doping that he devalues
the importance of motivation. Does the same apply if he enhances his motivation
artificially? I would suggest it does not. There is an important difference
between the enhancement of effectiveness and the enhancement of
motivation. Enhancing our effectiveness devalues our motivation
whilst it is hard to see how enhancing our motivation could possibly devalue
motivation. Accepting the above means it might be possible to
admire an athlete who artificially enhances his motivation whilst at the same
time failing to admire an athlete who simply enhances himself physically.
At this point someone might object that whilst accepting
someone who enhances his motivation does not devalue his motivation that
nonetheless he devalues himself as a person. He does so by making himself less
authentic. My objector might then argue someone shouldn’t enhance his motivation
because being authentic is something we value. In response I would point out
the things which make us authentic aren’t fixed from birth, babies aren’t
authentic. People seek to change themselves by enhancing themselves by training
or learning. I can see of no reason why people changing themselves by these
means will render themselves inauthentic. I would suggest someone’s authenticity
depends on him seeking goals he identifies with rather than the means he
chooses to seek these goals. Someone’s authenticity is determined by
what he loves or cares about. I would further suggest that a truly
authentic person must always choose those means which are most effective in
promoting the goals he identifies herself with. It follows if these
means include enhancing his motivation that this enhancement isn’t inauthentic.
Indeed, it appears that if someone doesn’t use the most effective means to
promote those goals he identifies with that his authenticity is weakened.
Sometimes those most effective means might include motivational enhancement and
it follows someone does not use motivational enhancement that his
authenticity is weakened
What conclusions can be drawn from the above. Firstly,
physical enhancement by artificial means devalues sport. Secondly motivational enhancement by
artificial means does not seem to conflict with the ethos of sport provided it
is accepted this ethos is connected to the sportsperson’s character. I accept
some people might be reluctant to accept this second conclusion and might
believe I am wrong to separate so completely the goals someone identifies with
and the means he uses to achieves his goals.
Wednesday, 29 June 2016
Outsourcing Ethical Decision Making and Authenticity
In a previous posting I questioned whether algorithmic assisted moral decision making is possible. Let us assume for the sake of argument that AAMD is possible. Using such a system might be considered as an example of algorithmic outsourcing of our moral decision making. Such outsourcing according to John Danaher means taking away the cognitive and emotional burden associated with certain activities, see Danaher . Intuitively outsourced moral decisions are inauthentic decisions. In this posting I will argue that under certain conditions outsourced ethical decisions using AAMD could be authentic ones.
- Christine Korsgaard, 2009, Self-Constitution, Oxford University Press, page 3.
- Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge University Press, page 103.
Wednesday, 25 May 2016
Cosmetic Surgery, Enhancement and the Aims of Medicine
- Jessica Laimann, 2015, Should we Prohibit
Breast Implants? Journal of
Practical Ethics 3(2)
- Silver M, 2003, Lethal injection,
autonomy and the proper ends of medicine, Bioethics 17(2).
Engaging with Robots
In an interesting paper Sven Nyholm considers some of the implications of controlling robots. I use the idea of control to ask a different...
-
In his posting on practical ethics Shlomit Harrosh connects the rights of death row inmates in certain states of the USA to choose the met...
-
According to Max Wind-Cowie shame should be liberated rather than legislated for. By this I take Wind-Cowie to mean that shame should pl...
-
Kristjan Kristjansson argues too much attention is paid to promoting an individual’s self esteem and not enough to promoting his self res...