In this posting I want to investigate the midlife crisis
and use my investigation to examine what is meant by having meaning in life.
The starting point for this for investigation is Kieran Setiya’s paper on the midlife
crisis .
What do we mean by the midlife crisis? The term midlife
crisis was first used by Elliot Jaques in 1965 to describe a period of unstable
mental or emotional health occurring in the middle of someone’s life. This
period might be triggered by someone becoming aware of her own mortality, the
death of someone close or a sense of lack of achievement in life and other
factors. In this posting I want to consider the midlife crisis from a
philosophical viewpoint. According to Setiya the midlife crisis, is a crisis of
meaning, someone suffering from the midlife crisis finds his life lacks
meaning. In what follows I will adopt Setiya’s definition.
Adopting this definition has several consequences. Firstly
it means that whilst becoming aware of one’s own mortality might well trigger a
midlife crisis, this awareness is not an essential element of that crisis. Indeed
an immortal might suffer such a crisis as Setiya suggests. Secondly a midlife
crisis does not of necessity have to occur in midlife. Setiya considers John
Stuart Mill’s nervous breakdown to be a midlife crisis even though this
occurred when Mill was only 20. It should be remarked Mill learnt Greek aged 3
and read Plato at 7 so perhaps he was older mentally than his 20 years. Thirdly it is important to be clear that
Setiya does not consider a lack of meaning to mean that someone suffering from
a midlife crisis believes everything lacks value. It is perfectly possible to
imagine a doctor suffering from a midlife crisis who nonetheless believes her
practise of medicine is of value to her patients.
I now want to consider some of the reasons given for this
lack of meaning in someone’s life. Mill was a social reformer and believed in
remedying society’s ills. It possible to imagine that his midlife crisis
depended on the thought that if all these ills were remedied that his life
would become meaningless. Accepting the above would mean a world lacking all
ills, a semi perfect world, would be one lacking a sense of meaning, such an
idea is dealt with in fiction by Matt Haig in his book “The Humans”. It follows
that whilst some people might find remedying the ills of society a sufficient
condition for a meaningful life it is not a necessary one. Setiya considers
that someone might believe her life is “just one dammed thing after another”
and that this belief is the cause of her life lacking meaning. If this is the
causes a lack of meaning and triggers a midlife crisis it is easy to see an
immortal might suffer from such a crisis. It might be suggested that if someone
has a sense of narrative about her life that she will not lack a sense of
meaning. Setiya is sceptical about of such a suggestion. He believes it is
perfectly possible for someone to lead an episodic life lacking narrative and
unity and nonetheless have a meaningful life. For instance someone might see
herself as a child then a parent followed by being a parent and then a
grandparent.
Of course I accept that there are episodes in someone’s
life. Nonetheless I believe that a completely episodic life is a meaningless
life. Christine Korsgaard believes that by choosing we constitute ourselves
(1). It seems to me that someone must
choose on the basis of what we ‘cares about’ or loves. If she doesn’t then it
further seems to me that she must lead a wanton or meaningless life. According
to Harry Frankfurt,
“caring about oneself is essential to being a person. Can
something to whom its own condition and activities do not matter in the
slightest properly be regarded as a person at all.” (2)
The way I use the term ‘caring about’ here means that if
someone ‘cares about’ something she invests in it and identifies herself with what she ‘cares about’ because she makes
herself vulnerable to losses and susceptible to benefits depending on whether
what she cares about is harmed or benefitted (3). I
regard ‘caring about’ as a basic form of love, see The
Structure of Love and Anti-Love Drugs . Let us accept that caring
about ‘caring about’ or loving is essential to being a person. I now want to argue
that because ‘caring about’ something is constitutive of being a person that
someone cannot lead a purely episodic life. Intuitively if someone ‘cares
about’ something this ‘caring about’ must have some persistence. Let us assume
that people usually ‘care about’ several things and that ‘caring about’
different things has differing persistence. It follows that to be a person
someone must have a sense of persistence, of narrative. It further follows that
the episodes in someone’s life must be connected or our ‘caring about’ would
have no persistence. Perhaps someone who sees herself progressing from being a
child to a grandparent might view this progression as a series of connected
chapters in her life rather than unconnected episodes.
I now want to return to Setiya’s analysis of the midlife
crisis. Setiya starts his analysis by considering our activities. Some of our
activities are done for some other end, these are classed as telic activities.
I walk from home to the bus stop in order to get to work. Some of our
activities a done for no other end, these are classed as atelic activities. I
go for a walk simply because it’s a nice day and I fancy being out in the
sunshine. It follows the same activity can be telic or atelic. Interestingly an
activity might be telic and atelic at the same time. I might walk from home to
the bus stop in order to get to work and because it’s a sunny day whilst I
usually get a lift to the stop. According to Setiya the midlife happens when
someone makes an excessive investment in telic activities, as ends, and not
means.
What are the implications of accepting Setiya’s definition
of a midlife crisis? Setiya’s definition allows us to see why an immortal might
suffer a midlife crisis and why someone suffering from such a crisis can still
see value in the world. However does such an understanding allow us to offer
advice to someone suffering from a midlife crisis or help her to help herself? It
seems clear that we offer advice. You can advise someone to seek more atelic ends
in her life. Simple we can resolve the midlife crisis! Unfortunately this isn’t
simple because whilst someone may seek more atelic ends her seeking doesn’t
mean she can simply acquire atelic ends. For something to become someone’s end
she must love or ‘cares about’ it. According to Frankfurt “the will of the
lover is rigorously constrained. Love is not a matter of choice.” (3) It follows
someone cannot simply decide to love something, acquire atelic ends, in order
to acquire meaning in her life and by doing so cure a midlife crisis. In Meaning
Love and Happiness I suggested whilst we cannot simply choose to
love that we might situate ourselves in situations in which love might grow
naturally. It follows the best advice we can give someone in life is to place
herself in situations in which love, as defined by ‘caring about’ can grow
naturally and hope by doing so she may acquire some atelic ends. In conclusion
we might point several things that might lead to more atelic ends such as,
friendship, parenthood, the pursuit of knowledge and caring for others.
- Christine
Korsgaard, 2009, Self-Constitution, Oxford University Press, page 24.
- Harry
Frankfurt, 1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge
University Press. Page 90
- Harry
Frankfurt, 1988, The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge
University Press, page 83.
- Frankfurt,
1999, page 135.
No comments:
Post a Comment