- Frankfurt 1988, The
Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University Press,
page 83.
- Frankfurt,
1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge University
Press, page 106.
- Frankfurt,
1999, page 90.
- Frankfurt,
1999, page 89.
This blog is concerned with most topics in applied philosophy. In particular it is concerned with autonomy, love and other emotions. comments are most welcome
Thursday, 25 August 2011
Riots and the Unbearable Lightness of Simply Being
Thursday, 11 August 2011
Zero Degrees of Empathy and Evil
In this posting I want to set out some thoughts about evil and empathy rather than pursuing a specific argument. My starting point is Simon Baron-Cohen’s book (2011, Zero Degrees of Empathy,
“Empathy is our ability to identify what someone else is thinking or feeling, and to respond to their thoughts and feelings with an appropriate emotion.” (Page 11)
However it might be questioned whether a lack of empathy is really directly connected to evil. Consider the Milgram experiments. These experiments involved the participants in giving what they believed to be very large electric shocks to a learner. In practice there were no real shocks and the learner was really an actor who faked his response. This experiment raises two questions. Firstly were the participants doing something evil? It seems clear to me they were. Secondly did these participants lack empathy? There were 40 volunteer participants in the trial all male whose ages ranged between 20 and 50 and whose jobs ranged from unskilled to professional. Let it be accepted that sociopaths who lack all empathy can commit evil acts. However it seems improbable to me that Milgram could have picked 40 sociopaths for his experiment and that at least some of the participants must have had some degree of empathy. It follows evil acts can be committed by both people who lack and possess empathy.
Baron-Cohen suggests that the extremes of evil are usually relegated to the unanalysable, see page 100. The question immediately arises why do we want to analyse the term evil? Perhaps analysing the term evil might be useful in some contexts? Consider the case of Josef Fritzl who imprisoned and raped his daughter Elisabeth. It seems to me the term evil is useful in this context by simply expressing our moral disgust at Fritzl’s actions. To re-describe Fritzl’s actions as lacking in empathy rather than evil would seem to be much less effective way of expressing our disgust. The term evil simply doesn’t need analysing in this context. However the term evil may have other uses. Baron-Cohen further suggests we can replace the terms ‘evil’ and ‘cruelty’ with the term ‘empathy’ in relation to those with zero negative empathy, see page 65. I will assume here by ‘empathy’ he means ‘lack of empathy’. It seems obvious that simply labelling people like Fritzl simply as evil is not useful in the context of explaining their actions. This context includes both the causes of evil and the way it spreads. Indeed in this context such simple labelling prevents explanation. In the rest of this posting I want to examine the causes of evil and the reasons for its spread. In order to do so I want to differentiate between two categories of people who commit evil acts. Firstly there are people who do evil acts but who do not conceive the acts. They simply propagate these acts. Secondly some people cause evil, originate the evil acts that they and others propagate.
I will consider those who cause, originate, evil first. It seems to me there are three main reasons why people originate evil. Firstly they commit an evil act when pursuing some other goal; for instance the CEO of some company, who knowingly lets his company pollute the environment near to a factory, hereby causing birth defects, in order to maximise profits. Secondly some people simply enjoy the infliction of suffering. Lastly evil is committed to further some greater cause; for instance the purification of the Germanic race or a jihad against the infidels. In this last case the perpetrators of evil may actually see themselves as acting for the best especially if they understand morality in a utilitarian way. None of the above reasons for the origin of evil depend directly on the perpetrators of evil having zero degrees of empathy. The CEO may love his wife and children. The torturer who enjoys suffering may actually need some partial form of empathy with his victim in order to increase his pleasure. He needs the ability to identify what his victim is thinking or feeling even if he lacks an appropriate response. And lastly a Jihadist may have started his Jihad because of his empathy for fellow Moslems. In the light of the above it would appear there is nothing to be gained by simply re-describing people who originate evil as people possessing near zero degrees of empathy rather than evil people. Nonetheless it is true that some people who originate evil acts do have a zero degree of empathy. Does having a zero degree explain the origin of evil in these cases? It would appear not. For as Baron-Cohen points out people with Asperger Syndrome and mild autism often develop a moral code through systemizing rather than empathy and as a result would appear to be no more likely to originate evil than anyone else, see page 84. It would appear having a zero degree of empathy is not useful in explaining why some people originate evil.
Nonetheless Baron-Cohen is correct to connect evil and empathy. A lack of empathy may not originate evil but if someone has sufficient empathy his empathy might act like a vaccine preventing him from originating evil. Sufficient empathy may be very important in controlling what we can think of as permissible. Indeed I would suggest that in the Western World the re-description of the civilian victims of bombing as collateral damage might be seen as an unconscious, at least I hope unconscious, attempt to limit our empathy. After all we describe famine victims as victims and not as the collateral damage caused by drought. It is an interesting question as to what proportion of evil doers are capable of originating evil. Perhaps this question is open to empirical research.
I now want to consider the possible causes for the propagation of evil? I would suggest three main interconnected causes. Firstly it seems clear from the Milgram experiment that respect for authority is a factor. In this experiment the experimenter told the teacher either it was essential to continue, the experiment required that he continue or that he had no choice but to go on. The experimenter would seem to be a figure of some authority. The second cause is linked to the first. Most people seem to find some sort of reassurance that what they are doing the right thing if others behave in a similar fashion. The Herd Instinct seems to confer some sort of legitimacy to their actions. The Herd Instinct means people tend to act as others do and their individuality declines. Lastly if the number of people contributing to an evil act is large enough individuals may not see themselves as really responsible for the act. The trouble is no one else may see themselves as responsible for the act. I argued in my posting of 24/05/11 that in such situations responsibility becomes smeared, see also Parfit (1984, Reasons and Persons,
What then might be done to combat the propagation of evil? I argued above a lack of empathy does not cause someone to propagate evil. In addition I suggested if someone has sufficient empathy his empathy might act like a vaccine preventing him from originating evil. I believe this suggestion also applies to the propagation of evil. Intuitively it seems plausible that increasing someone’s empathy might help him resist both authority and herd pressure in his dealings with others. I am however doubtful that increasing someone’s empathy will make him more aware of his responsibilities. Empathy might be increased in at least three ways. Firstly, John Bowlby’s attachment theory shows that children who experience stable loving parenting are likely to grow up well adjusted to the world. This good adjustment may be partly due to an increased capacity to feel empathy, see my posting of 30/03/09. Attachment theory predicts trans-generational effects so it follows that society should take active steps to enable parents, especially mothers, who experienced attachment problems as children become good parents. Someone might object I am encouraging the nanny state and that parenting is a purely personal matter. Let it be accepted bad parenting harms children. Mill argued “that the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.” (1859, On
Secondly it is possible that individual empathy flourishes better in less individualistic and more caring societies. Robert Cialdini’s work has shown if we give someone something he is likely to reciprocate, see http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Robert_Cialdini. Cialdini’s work is based on giving and not on expressing an emotion. However it seems plausible that the expression of an emotion leads others to reciprocate. Anger leads to anger and perhaps empathy to empathy. It is possible that a more empathic society might increase individual empathy. Someone might object that the above is too simplistic. He might point out there are angry people, empathic people but there are no angry or empathic societies. I accept my objectors point. I would however suggest societies in which people feel at ease are societies which contain less angry and more empathic individuals. I would further suggest people might feel more at ease in caring, giving societies. Lastly in a more speculative vein in the future we might be able to enhance our natural empathy by biomedical means. For instance Paul Zak has shown oxytocin delivered as a nasal spray increases our natural empathy, see http://www.luiss.it/esa2007/programme/papers/3.pdf .
In the light of the above it might appear that we should embrace all three of these means of increasing our natural empathy in order to combat the spread of evil. However I would urge caution. Firstly caution is needed with all biomedical enhancements. Secondly the above appearance depends on the assumption that increased empathy will reduce evil. However we should consider exactly how empathy might be increased. Empathy might be increased in two ways. Firstly empathy might be increased by increasing the empathy we feel towards those people who we already feel empathic concern for. Secondly it might be increased by increasing the range of people we feel empathic concern for; it might increase our domain of empathic concern. I would suggest simply increasing empathy, whilst desirable, is not always useful in combating the spread of evil. For instance if the empathy Germans felt for Germans under the third Reich had been increased it is extremely doubtful whether this increase would have prevented the Holocaust. It follows if we are serious about using increased empathy to combat the spread of evil that we must pay attention to increasing the domain of empathy in addition to increasing empathy in general.
The second cause of the propagation of evil I mentioned above was the herd instinct. For instance when crossing the road a Leeds University study discovered pedestrians are likely to act as a herd, blindly following other pedestrians, see http://www.physorg.com/news/2010-11-pedestrians-herd-instinct-road.html . It therefore seems quite plausible someone might blindly follow others, the herd, in propagating evil. One way of combating the herd instinct is to encourage individuality. It might then be suggested encouraging empathy damages individuality. Accepting this suggestion gives us a further reason to be cautious about simply increasing our empathy if we are seriously thinking about combating evil. However I would reject such a suggestion. I don’t believe building a more caring society must inevitably damage individuality. Firstly if we attempt to increase empathy by encouraging good parenting it seems likely any increase in empathy will not damage individuality. In what follows I will assume individuality means the capacity to act autonomously. Bowlby’s attachment theory predicts children with firm attachment will be more confident in exploring relationships with others. This confidence should increase rather than decrease their capacity to act autonomously. Moreover this confidence to explore their relationships with others should expand the domain of their empathic concern. The second way in which we might encourage empathy I listed above was to foster more caring and giving societies. I see no reason why increasing empathy by this means should damage individuals capacity for autonomy provided this is done from a position of epistemic humility. I believe truly beneficent care must involve adopting a position of epistemic humility, see my posting of 19/06/08. Building a more caring society from such a position means we must give priority to respecting the autonomy of others and provided we do so we should not damage individuality. Unfortunately even if we increase empathy by building a more caring society does not automatically follow that we increase the domain of our empathic concern, which is what I have suggested, is really needed to combat evil. It seems to me that the way our society is structured may be much more likely to increase empathy than by increasing how much it cares. Lastly it seems it may be possible to enhance our natural empathy by biomedical means. I would argue such enhancement should not be attempted if it damages our capacity for autonomy. In addition there appears to be some evidence from Zak’s experiments that such enhancement may only increase our empathic concern for those we already feel some empathy for, rather than expanding the domain of our empathic concern.
I have considered using increased empathy like a vaccine to combat the spread of evil caused by either deference to authority or an inability to resist the herd instinct. However I have suggested increasing empathy may not increase our sense of responsibility. In addition men as a whole feel less empathy than women. Lastly there are some people are incapable of feeling any empathy at all. In the light of these facts are there then any other means of combating the spread of evil? It is possible that increasing individuality might help in combating the spread of evil. I would suggest seeing ourselves as individuals rather than part of a herd increases our ideas of responsibility. Individuality can only flourish in a tolerant society and it might appear that a tolerant society is simply one accepting Mill’s dictum “that the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.” However as with the domain of empathic concern mentioned above there might be a problem with the domain of ‘civilised community’. For instance a large number of whites in apartheid
In conclusion I would suggest the methods discussed above can control the spread of evil acts to some degree. Unfortunately I believe these methods will do less to prevent the occurrence of evil acts such as those committed recently in Norway by Anders Behring Breivik.
Monday, 27 June 2011
Knobe, Erler and our ‘True Self’
In this posting I want to consider the comments by Alexandre Erler in Practical Ethics on an article by Joshua Knobe in the New York Times concerning personal identity see http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2011/06/what-is-my-true-self/#more-1548. Knobe uses the example of the evangelical preacher Mark Pierpont who encourages homosexuals to seek a “cure” for their sexual orientation. Pierpont himself was a homosexual and continues to battle his continuing homosexual urges. Knobe uses him as an example to question what is meant by someone’s ‘true self’. He firstly presents two common concepts of self. The first concept is an unreflective one in which our true self is determined by our nature, our urges. The second concept, as advocated by such as David DeGrazia, holds that our true self is defined by our commitments, values, and endorsements. Knobe suggests both of these concepts are challenged by the case of Pierpont. He further suggests that people regard the traits they value in someone as part of that person’s true self. In this posting I want to question whether the concept of someone’s true self as opposed to simply self is a useful concept.
To whom might the concept of a true self be useful? Firstly it might be useful to someone deciding what to do. She might ask what her true self would do in this situation when making some important decision. She might ask herself if she is acting authentically; to her own self being true. Secondly another may question what, is someone else’s true self, before ascribing praise or blame and predicting what that person will do. Intuitively it seems to me these two uses of the idea of true self are distinct and that a different concept might be useful in each case. I will deal with the second case first.
Knobe suggests that others regard the traits they value in someone as reflecting her ‘true self’. I would suggest any such concept of ‘true self’ should not help them ascribe praise or blame and it is not very useful in predicting the actions of others. Praise and blame seem to be more naturally connected to someone’s autonomy rather than her ‘true self’. Of course I accept that someone’s ‘true self’ may be connected to her autonomy. Nonetheless I believe the ascription praise and blame depends directly on someone’s autonomy and that there is no need to involve the concept of ‘true self’. It is plausible that understanding a person’s values might be useful in predicting her actions. However if our concept of ‘true self’ is limited to the values we approve of then this concept will be useful in predicting what we think someone should do rather than what she actually will do. For these reasons Knobe’s suggested concept of someone’s ‘true self’ does not seem to me to be a useful one when applied to others. Erler suggests that our ‘true self’ might be a composite of the two concepts Knobe introduced initially; our natural idea of a ‘true self ‘and an idea of a ‘true self’ being defined by our values and commitments. Is then Erler’s suggested composite concept any more useful than that of Knobe in this context? Once again I would suggest the ascription of praise and blame should be concerned with the idea of someone’s autonomy rather than her ‘true self’. Erler’s suggested concept may well be more useful in predicting someone’s actions but I wonder whether there is any useful difference in this particular context between the concepts of self and ‘true self’.
Is then any concept of a ‘true self’ useful to someone making a decision? Most ordinary decisions are largely unreflective and we just act without questioning our motives too much. However for some big decisions such as whether to pursue a particular career or start a family much more reflection is usually involved. Perhaps in these cases we might question what our ‘true self’ would do; what is the authentic thing to do. It seems clear to me if someone accepts her ‘true self’ is defined only by the values others value in her and she acts in accordance with this concept then she isn’t acting authentically. Knobe’s suggestion about true self is not useful in this context either. Let us return to the second concept of ‘true self’ initially introduced by Knobe. I would argue our deeply held commitments, values, and endorsements are what we ‘care about’. According to Harry Frankfurt if someone ‘cares about’ something she identifies herself with what she cares about and makes herself vulnerable to losses and susceptible to benefits depending on whether what she cares about is diminished or enhanced, see (1988, The Importance of What We Care About, Cambridge University Press, page 83.) Prima facie it might be assumed this concept of ‘true self seems to be a useful concept for someone to employ when deciding how to make some big decision and there is no need for Erler’s composite definition. Prior to making that decision they ask themselves what they really ‘care about’. It would further seem when Pierpont encourages homosexuals to seek a “cure” for their sexual orientation he is acting in accordance with this concept of his ‘true self’. He is acting authentically.
I believe it is certainly true people act with respect to what they ‘care about’. This concept of ‘true self’ determines their actions. However even if it is accepted that one’s ‘true self’ determines one’s actions it does not automatically follow that one’s true self is useful in deciding what to do. What someone intends to do and what he ‘cares about’ need not be identical.
Wednesday, 1 June 2011
Sexually Coercive Offers
Tuesday, 24 May 2011
Roboethics and Autonomy
- Wendell
Wallach, Colin Allen, 2009, Moral
Machines, Oxford University Press, page 20.
Tuesday, 26 April 2011
Medical Ethics and Thoroughgoing Autonomy
Before making my defence I must make clear the position I am defending. I do not believe autonomy is the only principle relevant to medical ethics. Even if some form of medical ethics could be based solely on patient autonomy, which I doubt, the ethos of medicine depends on the notion of caring. I accept beneficence is of major importance to medical ethics. Foster characterizes the form of autonomy he is attacking as an icy, unattractive, Millian, absolutist version of autonomy. I do not believe such a form of autonomy should form the basis of most medical ethics. Firstly I will argue a more user friendly concept of autonomy should be applied in medical ethics. I will then argue this concept of autonomy is not subject to the same problems as a more absolutist version. Lastly I will defend the position that respecting the autonomous wishes of a patient should always be given precedence over acting beneficently towards him.
I argued in my posting of 03/09/10 that an autonomous decision is simply a decision with which the agent identifies himself and “cares about”; in this context I am using “cares about” in the same way as Harry Frankfurt, see for instance (1999, Necessity, Volition, and Love, Cambridge University Press). An autonomous decision is one the agent is wholehearted about. Frankfurt argues a wholehearted decision is one with which the agent is satisfied with. He defines satisfaction as an absence of restlessness or any desire for change. If we accept this concept of autonomy then it has consequences for the autonomous decisions patients make. I argued in my posting of 01/07/08 that this form of autonomy is closely connected to the idea of satisficing. It follows patients can make autonomous decisions which are sub-optimal. But don’t some patients such as Jehovah’s Witnesses already make sub-optimal decisions in practice? Moreover a patient may also make an autonomous decision simply to trust his medical team to do what they believe is best for him. In reality I would suggest this is what most patients implicitly do when making a consent decision. This after all is how many of us explicitly make decisions outside a medical context. We simply trust lawyers or financial advisors for instance, without others questioning our autonomy. Are doctors less trustworthy than lawyers or financial advisors?
Foster believes a Millian absolutist version of autonomy causes problems for medical ethics. I agree with Foster. But does a concept of autonomy based on “caring about” cause the same problems? In what follows I will argue it does not. Firstly Foster seems to assume autonomy requires that agents are able to give an unequivocal answer to the question what do you want? He then suggests it is unusual to meet someone who is so well integrated as to be able to do so. I agree many people have difficulty giving an unequivocal answer to the question, what do you want? But how is this difficulty connected to medical ethics? It seems to me Foster must believe that informed consent requires a patient is able to give an unequivocal answer to what he wants. In medical practice a patient is seldom, if ever, asked what treatment he wants. Rather the question usually posed is simply this; “we believe this treatment is in your best interests do you give your consent?” The validity of this consent is of course dependent on the patient being given adequate information about the relevant details of the proposed treatment. If we conceive autonomy as “caring about” linked to satisfaction then autonomous decisions are also not linked to someone being able to give an unequivocal answer to the question what do you want? Autonomy is simply linked to an absence of any desire on the part of a patient to change his decision. Unequivocal answers are only required when a patient doesn’t want some treatment. The above suggests if autonomy is conceived as “caring about” that Foster’s worry about medical practice and respecting autonomy being incompatible because patients cannot always give unequivocal answers when giving informed consent is not justified.
Secondly Foster worries that the giving informed consent in clinical practice is linked to the giving of informed consent in clinical trials. Foster states informed consent requires that a patient in a consultation with a surgeon about his osteoarthritic hip talks in much the same way as a subject in a clinical trial would talk with the trial’s co-ordinator. I once again agree. However I believe if an autonomous decision depends on an agent’s satisfaction with this decision there is no good reason based respect for autonomy why the above linkage should not be broken. For instance I suggested above a patient may make an autonomous decision simply to trust his medical team to do what they believe is in his best interests because doctors are no less trustworthy than lawyers or financial advisors. Different agents may need different amounts of information to make a decision that satisfies them. Moreover an agent might need different amounts of information in order to satisfy him make a decision in different situations. For instance if I am going to have my blood pressure taken all I need to know is I am going to have my blood pressure taken. If I am going to have an operation for my osteoarthritic hip I may need information about the benefits and risks involved. I may only need to understand the risks involved in very broad terms as the pain in my hip means I will discount these to some degree. If however I am consenting to take part in a clinical trial I need to be better informed about any risks involved as I have no factors which will make me discount these risks. In the light of the above I see no reason based on respect for autonomy why the information needed to give consent to treatment should comparable to the information needed to consent to take part in a clinical trial.
Lastly Foster mentions an important paper by Agledahl, Forde and Wifstad (Journal of Medical Ethics 2011; 37) see http://jme.bmj.com/content/37/4/212.full?sid=7a5d7b0f-c5e1-4291-838e-b0d9414fc1d2 . Agledahl, Forde and Wifstad state “patients' right to autonomous choice is upheld as an ideal although the options of both the patients and the doctors are very limited” and then they rightly point out that “in the healthcare setting, choices are often neither explicit nor available.” The implication of the above seems to be that the authors believe a lack of choice means concern for patient autonomy is basically a sham. Let it be accepted all competent patients have some choice. All competent patients can consent or refuse to consent to treatment. I would suggest if autonomy is based on “caring about” linked to satisfaction that in a clinical setting concern for autonomy is not a sham. It is not a sham because a doctor does not have to offer a patient an array of options out of concern for his autonomy. One option is all that is needed. Indeed accepting a concept of autonomy based on “caring about” might mean in a clinical setting too many choices actually erode a patient’s autonomy. Frankfurt argues,
‘For if the restrictions on the choices that a person in a position to make are relaxed too far, he may become, to a greater or lesser degree, disorientated with respect to where his interests and preferences lie.’ (1999, page 109).
In the light of the above I would suggest the fact patients have limited options does not mean it is impossible to respect patient autonomy in practice.
It might be argued the concept of autonomy I have outlined above is an amorphous concept offering little practical guidance. If this is so it might be asked how I am going to defend a thoroughgoing autonomist’s position. Foster argues we need to embrace a truly liberal pluralism that listens respectfully to the voices of many principles. It seems to the soundness of his position depends on what he means by pluralism. I believe if pluralism means some sort of competition between different moral goods the result would be incoherence. I would suggest the only way to avoid this incoherence is to give priority to some moral goods. This prioritization does not imply we must be able to weigh moral goods but that we must be able to rank them. I will now argue this prioritization means giving precedence to respecting autonomy over acting beneficently. If I am going to act beneficently towards someone I must care for him. The basis of my care may be sympathy or empathy. If my beneficence is based on sympathy it seems clear to me that I may act in what I conceive to be his best interests and override his autonomy. If however my beneficence is based on empathy this option is not open to me. If I feel empathy for someone I must focus on what he cares about rather than what I think might be in his best interests. It follows if I want to act beneficently towards someone, and my beneficence is based on empathic concern rather than sympathy and I believe his best interests clash with his autonomy, I should nevertheless give precedence to respecting his autonomy over acting in these interests. Beneficence based on empathy automatically gives precedence to respecting autonomous decisions. It follows if beneficence is based on empathy it is possible to defend a thoroughgoing autonomist’s position. Agledahl, Forde and Wifstad seem to partially support my position because they believe “the right to refuse treatment is fundamental and important”. If autonomy is based on “caring about” and beneficent care based on empathy then a limited thoroughgoing autonomist’s position means doctors need not concern themselves to much with providing choices but must respect all autonomous decisions. However an objector might point out I have provided no reason as to why beneficence should be based on empathy rather than sympathy. We can act beneficently towards animals. Clearly such beneficence is based on sympathy. I would suggest we cannot feel empathy for animals due to epistemic ignorance. I would further suggest we can act more beneficently towards people if our concern is empathic rather than sympathetic. It follows good beneficent care is based on empathic concern. Accepting my suggestions means medical ethics should be prepared to accept a limited thoroughgoing autonomist’s position. Indeed I would argue such a position concurs very well with the practice of medicine with the exception that accepting such a position would mean accepting a fully autonomous decisions by a patient simply to trust his clinicians as to which is the best course of treatment for him.
Thursday, 7 April 2011
Brooks, Brudner and Justice
Brudner believes we should punish others when they damage or threaten to damage our autonomy rather than because of any harm they cause us. Of course if we damage or threaten someone’s autonomy we harm them. In the light of the above I would suggest Brudner’s position might be described as follows. We should punish others only because of the harm they do to our autonomy and not because of any other harm. It is this re-described position I will consider in this posting even though it is by no means certain Brudner would entirely agree with my re-description. I have suggested the only requirement necessary for a truly flourishing society is that each of us should be free to do as she sees best provided by so doing she does not harm others. In the light of this suggestion it might appear to follow that I believe the basis of the law should be harm to others rather than restricted to harm an individual’s autonomy. This appearance is deceptive. Any harm to an autonomous agent always also harms her autonomy. If I harm an autonomous agent I do something to her which she would not do to herself. My actions prevent the agent from making a choice she would identify herself with or which satisfies her. My actions damage her autonomy. It follows all actions that harm autonomous agents also do harm to their autonomy.
Brooks believes Brudner’s position is unconvincing in some contexts. He points out “that there may be many actions we may want criminalized (e.g., traffic offences) that would not be clearly included” in any criminalization as defined by Brudner. Brooks also points out suicide, which ends the victim’s autonomy, and moderate alcohol use, which temporarily affects the user’s autonomy, both of which we would intuitively not want to be criminalized, might well be criminalized provided criminalization is based on harm to an agent’s autonomy. Someone might argue some traffic offences such as speeding have the potential to damage the autonomy of another and hence their criminalization can be justified on Brudner’s account. She might then proceed to point out it is possible to respect autonomy in different ways. Firstly it is possible to respect someone’s autonomous decisions and secondly to protect her capacity to make autonomous decisions. Let us assume a patient suffers from some incurable disease and makes an autonomous decision to commit suicide. If criminalization is justified by damage done by not respecting autonomous decisions rather than harm done to an agent’s capacity to make autonomous decisions then suicide and the moderate use of alcohol should not be criminalized. If criminalization is justified by damage to an agent’s capacity to make autonomous decisions then these actions should be prohibited. How do we choose between respecting autonomous decisions and protecting someone’s capacity to make these decisions? I have argued in previous postings respect for autonomy is intimately tied to respect for persons and it is impossible to respect persons if one doesn’t respect their decisions, see for instance http://woolerscottus.blogspot.com/2008_08_01_archive.html . If my arguments are accepted then it follows that whilst we must respect someone’s autonomous decisions and protect her capacity to make these decisions that when these two ways of respecting autonomy are incompatible we should give precedence to respecting autonomous decisions. It further follows Brudner’s justification of criminalization may be able to account for the cases Brooks raises.
Brooks states that he strongly agrees with Brudner’s focus on offering a political, not a moral, theory of punishment. I’m by no means sure this focus on a purely political basis is possible. It seems to me if we accept Brudner’s position, that the legality of some action depends on whether it harms or threatens to harm our autonomy, we must also implicitly accept that the domain of legal responsibility is the same as the domain of legal concern. Accepting the above means we must accept only all autonomous agents can be held legally responsible and it also means we must accept the domain of legal concern only extends as far as these agents. Accepting the domain of legal concern only extends as far as autonomous agents seems problematic. Clearly children are not fully autonomous agents and equally clearly a child is of legal concern even though she cannot be held to be legally responsible for her actions. In the case of children this problem might be overcome in the same way as traffic offences above. Brudner’s position might be slightly modified so that the legality of some action depends on whether it harms or threatens to harm our potential autonomy. However even if this modification is accepted a problem remains. Let us assume that animals cannot be autonomous. Clearly if a farmer or pet owner lets her animals starve to death the fate of these animals should be of legal concern. Even more clearly severely handicapped children and old people suffering from dementia should be of legal concern even though these people will never be autonomous.
In the light of the above it seems to me that the legality of an action cannot be based solely on political concerns about autonomy. Let it be accepted the only legal limitations a truly flourishing political society may impose on an agent’s autonomous decisions must be to limit the harm her decisions do to others. However what counts as harm is based sometimes depends on moral concerns completely unconnected to concerns about autonomy. Depending on the moral interpretation of what counts as harm the constraint of harm on the unbridled exercise of autonomy may vary greatly.
Engaging with Robots
In an interesting paper Sven Nyholm considers some of the implications of controlling robots. I use the idea of control to ask a different...
-
In his posting on practical ethics Shlomit Harrosh connects the rights of death row inmates in certain states of the USA to choose the met...
-
According to Max Wind-Cowie shame should be liberated rather than legislated for. By this I take Wind-Cowie to mean that shame should pl...
-
Kristjan Kristjansson argues too much attention is paid to promoting an individual’s self esteem and not enough to promoting his self res...