Few people seem to actively enjoy doing evil acts yet evil
seems to be widespread. In this posting I will examine what we mean by evil in
order to explain this discrepancy. Evil is a word we use all the time, for
instance terrorists and serial killers are often said to be evil. However if
saying something or someone is evil is to be useful, to be more than
condemnation, then we must be clear what we are talking about. In this
posting I will attempt to define a useful definition of evil and I will argue
that being evil isn’t a matter of degree, how bad we are, but is concerns with
how we are motivated. I will draw a definition between someone who is actively
evil and someone who is passively evil, This will lead me to conclude that someone
needn’t commit any evil acts or even have a disposition to do so in order to be
regarded as evil. Such a position might be regarded as an extreme one by some.
Evil is connected to harm. I will now introduce definitions
of an evil act and evil person as suggested by Luke Russell. Russell defines an
evil act as follows,
“An action is evil if and only if it is a wrong that is
extremely harmful for at least one individual victim, where the wrongdoer is
fully culpable for the harm in its extremity, or it is an action that is
appropriately connected to an actual or possible extreme harm of this kind and
the agent is fully culpable for that action” (1)
Russell defines an evil person as,
“You are an evil person if and only if you are strongly
disposed to perform evil action and this disposition is now so firmly fixed
that you ought to be treated as a write off.” (2)
These are thoughtful definitions and are a useful starting
point for our examination. However accepting these definitions makes it is
difficult to account for Hannah Arendt’s “banality of evil”. Moreover
intuitively whether an act, however bad, is regarded as evil seems dependent on
the definition of an evil person.
I now want to suggest a different account of evil.
Sometimes an evil person is contrasted with a virtuous person. Very roughly
speaking a virtuous person has a disposition to mostly do good. It might then
be suggested that an evil person mirrors this and is someone who has a
disposition to do evil. If we accept that an evil action is one which causes
great harm for which the agent is culpable then we are accepting a definition
akin to that of Russell. I now want to propose a different account of evil. According
to David Hume
“Tis not contrary to reason to
prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger”.
Perhaps such a person might be regarded rational, which I
wouldn’t, but we would certainly regard her as evil. The above suggests that
instead of having a disposition to do evil an evil person is simply someone who
lacks any disposition to do good when she is capable of doing so even and when
doing so would prevent extreme harm. Evil acts don’t require evil intentions
but a lack of motivation to do the good. However such a definition is
incomplete because using it someone who feels no moral pull because she is
incapable of understanding any moral requirements would be regarded as evil.
Surely we shouldn’t regard someone who is severely cognitively impaired as
evil. Someone who causes great harm but cannot understand any moral
requirements not to cause that harm is no more responsible for this harm than
the harm caused by an earthquake. I would suggest that an evil action cannot be
understood without reference to an agent understanding that the society she
lives in has moral requirements even if she doesn’t feel the pull of these
requirements. Moreover she must understand what these requirements entail. It
is important to be clear that by the inability to feel any moral pull isn’t the
same as the inability to understand moral requirements. It follows that if
someone is to be regarded as evil that she must be capable of understanding
some moral requirements. An evil person might be defined by the following two
conditions.
An evil person is someone who lacks any disposition to do
good when she is capable of doing so even when doing so would prevent extreme
harm.
An evil person is someone who is capable of understanding
moral requirements even if she feels no moral pull.
If we accept this definition then it is possible to define
an evil action.
An evil action is an extremely harmful act which an evil
person enacts or permits to be enacted.
Accepting these definitions means that we need to be able
to understand what it means to be an evil person before we can classify some
act as evil. It also means that someone need not be actively evil and she can
be passively evil. It is possible to differentiate between active and passive
evil. Lastly it means that hatred need play no part in evildoing.
This definition is similar to that of Simon Baron Cohen.
Baron Cohen wants to redefine evil as the erosion of empathy. (3) This
definition refers to evil acts rather than evil persons because whilst autistic
people lack empathy to some degree this lack doesn't make them evil. Indeed
many high functioning autistic people are attracted by rules and strongly feel
the pull of morality. This pull could be due to ‘caring about’ as the
defined by Harry Frankfurt or due to emotions unconnected to empathy. The
above definition is slightly different from that of Baron Cohen and might be
characterised by the inability or the erosion of the ability to feel the pull
of morality rather than empathy.
Let us now examine some of the consequences of accepting
the above definitions. According to Arendt Adolf Eichmann was an ordinary,
rather bland, bureaucrat who was neither perverted nor sadistic, but
‘terrifyingly normal. His motive according to Arendt motive was simply to
advance his career in the Nazi bureaucracy. According to Arendt’s account of
Eichmann he didn’t enjoy his evil deeds and didn’t have a strong disposition to
perform evil actions. It follows that we must reject either Russell’s
definition of an evil person or Arendt’s account of Eichmann. Is the definition
of an evil person outlined above more compatible with Arendt’s account of the
banality of evil? If we accept this definition then an evil person doesn’t have
to like to be attracted to evil she merely has to have no motivation not to do
evil, she is passively evil. Perhaps Eichmann didn’t enjoy sending Jews to
extermination camps but he had no motivation not to do so. It follows that
Eichmann fulfilled the first condition of an evil person. I would further
suggest that Eichmann must have understood that killing millions of people
contravened moral standards. Someone might object to the above and suggest
that the Nazis had introduced new moral standards. She might then suggest that
the situation Eichmann found himself was responsible for his evil acts rather
Eichmann himself. In response I would suggest the secrecy of the final solution
suggests that the Eichmann was well aware that he was breaking moral standards
and that even if the situation helped determine his actions that he felt no
unease at doing so. This failure to feel any moral unease made him an evil man.
Much of the above could be applicable in the case of Harold Shipman the British
serial killer who murdered around 250 victims. Except for one case Shipman had
no motive for murder and appeared to take no pleasure in his actions. However I
would suggest the above definition isn’t completely compatible with Arendt’s
views. Arendt suggested Eichmann was an ordinary, rather bland, bureaucrat I
would suggest that someone who lacks any motivation to prevent harm when she is
capable of doing so isn’t normal. Perhaps Eichmann was a bland bureaucrat but he
wasn’t ordinary, wasn’t orfinary.
A second consequence of accepting the above definition is
that someone might be an evil person but never actually do any evil acts, an
evil person might never be an evildoer. This consequence accords well with
Nicolas Bommarito’s idea of inner
virtue and vice. Such a thought seems to run counter to our
intuitions. However it seems possible that someone might have a generous
disposition but that she has never been generous because she lives in an
extremely deprived circumstances. Let us recall that an evil act must be an
extremely harmful one. It seems possible then that someone might live in
circumstances in which the opportunity for doing extremely harmful actions
doesn’t exist. In such circumstances someone might not be an evildoer but would
remain an evil person if she had a disposition to do evil even if she never
acted on it. However my definition is more radical than this, Someone can be an
evil person even if she never acts evilly or doesn’t have any disposition to
act evilly provided she doesn’t have any disposition to do good when she is
capable of doing so in order to prevent extreme harm. According to David Hume “all
that is necessary for evil to flourish is that good men do nothing” but if we
accept the above Hume’s ‘good men’ are actually passively evil. Consider
someone who sees a frail person fall in the street and struggle to get up and
has no motivation to help him then she should be regarded as an evil rather
than simply heartless. Omissions can point out evil. Perhaps if Eichmann had
been born in different times he would have been an ordinary bland, bureaucrat
who did no evil but nonetheless he would have remained an evil person.
According to the definition of evil we have adopted an evil
person feels no moral pull but must understand moral requirements. This leads
to the third consequence of accepting the above definition. Someone can only be
regarded as evil in reference to the moral standards they lived in. Moral
standards aren’t changed easily which I have suggested is one reason for the
Nazi’s secrecy about the Holocaust. Nonetheless moral standards do change over
longer periods of time. Let us consider slavery. Slavery is a great wrong today
and in our time anyone who kept a slave would be regarded as an evil person.
Let us now consider the Bristol slave trader Edward Colston. Let us accept that
he was a racist but was he also an evil person? If he felt the moral pull and
understood the moral requirements of his time then perhaps he wasn’t. The
question then becomes was slave trading morally acceptable in his times. This
is no means clear. Let us move on to consider an easy case, let us consider
Aristotle. Let us assume that Aristotle kept slaves if our assumption is
correct was he an evil person? If he felt the moral pull and understood the
moral requirements of his times then he wasn’t. I would suggest that keeping
slaves was morally acceptable in ancient Greece. In the light of the above it
would seem that we should judge people as evil or not according to how they
responded to the moral requirements of their time.
The fourth consequence of accepting the above definition
means that even if a good person can act badly that she cannot act evilly. Evil
acts are defined as extremely harmful actions performed by evil persons.
Accepting the above seems to run counter to our intuitions and appears to give
us a strong reason to reject the above account of evil. In Bernard Shaw's St
Joan a soldier is let out of hell for one day because he does a good thing by
giving Joan a straw cross. An evil person does a good thing. Surely if evil people can do good things then
good people can do evil things. The Milligram experiment shows good people can
do very bad things but is doing very bad things the same as acting evilly? Before
answering this question we must provide a rough definition of what we mean by a
good person. In what follows a good person will simply be defined as someone
who has a disposition to do good in most situations For the sake of argument
let us assume that a good person can act evilly. What reasons can be advanced
for a good person acting evilly? Firstly a good person might have a failure in
cognition and fail to see that she is acting evilly. Secondly her disposition
to do mostly good might be overwhelmed by other forces allowing her to act
evilly. Let consider the first of these explanations. Perhaps a good person
feels the pull of morality in general way but fails to fully understand what a
particular moral norm requires of her. For instance someone might understand
the moral norm not to be cruel to others but fail to include animals among
those others. Let us assume she is cruel to animals. Let us accept she acts
badly but it would seem hard to describe her actions as evil. More generally it
would seem hard to describe someone’s action as evil when she fails to fully
understand the moral implications of the action. If this wasn’t true then it
would be possible to describe the actions of someone who is severely
cognitively impaired as evil. Such a description seems to run counter to our
intuitions. It follows that a good person cannot act evilly because of a
failure in cognition.
Let us now consider the second explanation of how a good
person can act evilly. It might argued that a good person can act evilly if her
moral sentiments are overwhelmed by other forces. For instance a soldier’s
moral sentiments might be overwhelmed by rage at some atrocity and she in turn
commits a further atrocity. According to Seneca rage is a form of madness. If
so when someone’s disposition to do good is overwhelmed by rage she is
cognitively disabled and we are able to use the first explanation above to show
she isn’t acting evilly. However let us assume that whilst someone’s
disposition to do good is completely overwhelmed that she remains aware she is
acting badly. Can someone who can do no other said to be responsible for her
actions? Can some act be regarded as evil if the agent cannot be held to be
responsible for her actions? If the answers to these two questions are both negative
then good people can act badly but it would be wrong to describe those whose
disposition to do good are over whelmed by other forces as acting evilly. Such
a conclusion might have satisfied Socrates. Perhaps whilst good person can act
badly she can’t act evilly.
The fifth consequence of accepting the above means we might
question whether terrorists are really evildoers. Terrorists should rightly be regarded as cruel and callous
but should they also be regarded as evil? Terrorists have some sort of moral
code even if we might regard it as a warped one. If being evil depends on a
complete lack of any moral pull then it follows that terrorists aren’t evil.
Such a conclusion might not be totally unwelcome for perhaps terrorists might
be reformed by changing their moral concepts even if this change is extremely
difficult bring about, such a change might not be possible with evildoers such
as Eichmann.
The sixth consequence of accepting the above definitions means
we can’t label any organisation as evil. This seems counterintuitive. We can’t
label the Nazi party or a terrorist organisations as evil even if they foster
evil. Dictators and party members may be evil but the party can’t be evil for
to be evil some creature must be capable of understanding moral requirements. Organisations can’t understand moral
requirements and so can’t be evil.
Definitions should increase our understanding or be useful.
Does the above definition do either of these? Firstly the fact that an evildoer
doesn’t feel any moral pull doesn’t excuse her evil actions. If someone
knowingly does evil and could have acted otherwise then she can be held
accountable for her actions. However if the cause of evil is a failure to feel
any moral pull then this might be regarded as a mitigating factor. Secondly one
way to combat evil might be to look at how people fail to acquire a sense of
moral pull. Children naturally acquire some feeling of morality from their
parents and society. Perhaps extremely deprived or abusive childhoods erode a
child’s ability to acquire moral sentiments. Good parenting and education might
help children acquire these sentiments. Unfortunately some people might not
acquire these sentiments for physical reasons. Perhaps a low level of these
sentiments might be boosted by pharmacological means. In ‘unfit for the
Future’ Ingmar Persson and Julian Savulescu argue that there is a need for
moral enhancement in order to counter the existential dangers. (4) Perhaps more
limited targeted pharmacological enhancement might be used to prevent some
people from becoming evil, see psychopaths
and moral enhancement. Lastly the society we should try to make our
society one which decreases the likelihood of evil manifesting itself. I
suggested above that whilst Eichmann might have remained an evil man but that
in a better society that his evil might not have manifested itself.
- Luke Russell, 2020 Being Evil, Oxford University Press, page 87
- Russell, page 114
- Simon Baron-Cohen, 2011, Zero Degrees of Empathy, Allen Lane, page 4.
- Ingmar Persson & Julian Savulescu, 2012, UNFIT FOR THE FUTURE, Oxford University Press.