There is a tendency in
philosophy to believe we define ourselves. That we define ourselves by our
values or what we ‘care about’, see for instance Helm and Frankfurt .
“I have claimed that one’s
identity is fundamentally a matter of the kind of life worth living and that
this is determined largely by one’s personal priorities and values; ….Thus when
asked who I am I do not say a 6-4 –inch former soccer player who likes chocolate
and is susceptible to the gambler’s fallacy … I respond by saying that I am a
philosophy professor, father of three, etc.” (1)
“It is in the nature of a
lover’s concern that he is invested in his beloved. That is, he is benefited
when his beloved flourishes; and he suffers when it is harmed. Another way of
putting it is that the lover identifies himself with what he loves. This
consists of accepting the interests of his beloved as his own.” (2)
In this posting I do not want
to deny we partly define ourselves by our values or what we ‘care about’.
However I will suggest there is a tendency to overstate this self-definition.
Moreover I believe this overstatement applies to the importance of values and
what someone ‘cares about’ and ignores other things that help define her.
Helm when asked who he is
does not say he was a soccer player or that he likes chocolate and is
susceptible to the gambler’s fallacy but replies by choosing certain things he
values. Helm is identifying himself with his values and seems to assume others
will identify him in a similar way. However there are problems with this
approach. Firstly someone may be unaware of some of the values she possesses. Secondly
we must be careful about the idea of choice. As I noted in my previous posting
what someone values need not be identical with the values she explicitly
identifies with. She can be mistaken about some of her values. Our values are
determined just a much by what someone actually does as by what she thinks she
should do. I believe Helm would accept this point as he argues someone
sometimes discovers her values.
However even if someone is
unaware of some of her values, does she sometimes choose her values and in so doing
is she creating her identity like some existential hero? Personally I am
unhappy with such a position. Recent research in experimental philosophy has
shown that sometimes someone’s choices are influenced less by her character and
more by the situation she finds herself in; see for instance Appiah (3). It
follows someone’s choices may sometimes be determined less by her character and
more by her situation. It further follows some of someone’s values might well
be determined by the circumstances she finds herself in. Helm holds our
identity is determined by our values. It still further follows if we accept
Helm’s position that in practice someone’s identity is not simply chosen by
her. Accepting the above is one of the reasons I rather like Helm’s idea of
someone discovering her values; discovering her identity. In spite of the above
I do not want to completely downplay the role someone’s explicit choices about
value play in creating her identity, I only want argue such choices do not play
as big a part as we might assume. The fact someone has some value may in many
cases be partly be due to the fact she made a choice. But even if someone has genuinely
chosen something as a value does not guarantee it is in fact value. She must
also be able to live up to her choice. In some cases she may discover she
cannot, see Frankfurt discussion of Sartre’s
young man (4). It might be objected there is some circularity in the above
arguments concerning character, value and identity. I will not pursue this objection
here but believe it can be overcome, see (5).
Helm and Frankfurt
hold that our identity depends on what we value or ‘care about’. However I
would suggest the fact that we often appear to discover our identity means
other factors play a part in determining this identity. In my posting of 12/12/11
I argued that the fact someone suffers from Asperger’s syndrome partly
determines her identity. Asperger’s syndrome affects someone’s neural
development and hence the way she thinks, she chooses. I would go even further than
this and suggest factors independent of our neural makeup also affect our
identity. Consider someone born without legs and as a result of this is confined
to a wheelchair. I would argue this fact affects the choices open to her and
hence her identity. She may not for instance become a mountaineer like her
parents. An objector to the above might use my wheelchair example to argue against
me. She might argue if a soldier who loses his legs in Afghanistan and
becomes confined to a wheelchair that this does not change his identity. Our
intuitions about the mountaineer’s daughter and the wounded soldier seem to
lead us to a paradox. I believe this paradox can be resolved. I accept soldier’s
identity is not changed at the time of his injury but I would argue his
identity will be changed over time. Let us assume prior to his injury the
soldier identified himself with being a soldier leading his men into battle.
This option is now closed to him. Let us further assume that post his injury he
becomes a Para-Olympian and identifies himself with sport. It would appear then
that over time the fact he has become a wheelchair user has in some ways affected
his identity.
I have argued that in practice
someone’s identity is not simply chosen by her but is also determined by her
physical body and the circumstances she finds herself in. Part of these
circumstances is the way other people see her. It follows our identity is
linked to the way others see us. Let us return to a soldier example. Let us
assume our soldier is a paramedic who does not see herself as brave. Let us
further assume one day she tends to a wounded colleague under enemy fire. Her
colleagues see her as brave and because of this she discovers herself to be
brave. Of course she was brave before her discovery but her bravery was
unreflective whilst after her discovery her bravery came to play a more central
part in her life, in her identity and this centrality would not have happened
had not others seen her as brave.
1.
Bennett Helm,
2010, Love, Friendship & the Self,
Oxford University Press, page 130.
2.
Harry Frankfurt
2006, Taking Ourselves Seriously, Stanford University
Press, Page 41.
3.
Kwame Appiah,
2008, Experiments in Ethics, Harvard
University Press, chapter 2.
4.
Frankfurt , 1988, The
Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University Press, page 84.
5.
Helm, page 140.
No comments:
Post a Comment